Access Provided by Fordham University Library at 12/08/12 9:37PM GMT Transactions of the American Philological Association 142 (2012) 295–328 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia: Examples of Homeric Exegesis in Terms of Mathematical Geography tomislav bilić Archeological Museum, Zagreb summary: Crates of Mallos, a Hellenistic grammarian and geographer, is known to have combined Homeric exegesis and mathematical geography into a comprehensive world-view. His views appear to have influenced a tradition of map-making, as evidenced by an unusual late antique map that locates parts of Odysseus’s voyage from Aeaea to Hades according to Crates’ geography. This essay elucidates Crates’ geographical accounts of the Homeric Laestrygonians and of the constellation Draco and his understanding of the arctic circle in light of the map and of earlier geographers, particularly Pytheas of Massalia, who similarly incorporated Homeric references into his theorizing about the fixed arctic circle. introduction crates of mallos, aristarchus’s “arch-enemy,” was a second-century b.c.e. grammarian (he would have prefered the title kritikos),1 whose contribution to Homeric exegesis is increasingly acknowledged and studied in its own right.2 His contributions to geography, however, are in general not judged favorably: he is described “bestenfalls als interessierter und ver- Fr. 94, cf. T 1, 20; fr. 59. Crates’ fragments are generally cited according to Broggiato 2001 (fr., T); otherwise, according to Mette 1936. Broggiato is currently preparing a new edition of Crates for FGrHist 5 (Brill online), and I would like to thank her for giving me the opportunity to study the section of her manuscript pertaining to the subject of my paper (cited as Broggiato forthcoming). On the terms grammatikos/kritikos/Homerikos with reference to Crates, see Asmis 1992: 138–39; Porter 1992: 85–86, cf. 87–88; Broggiato 2001: xx, 249–50. 2 See, e.g., Kroll 1922; Mette 1936; Quinn 1982: 97–108; Asmis 1992; Porter 1992, 2003; Broggiato 2001: xiii–lxix. 1 © 2012 by the American Philological Association 296 Tomislav Bilić gleichsweise gut orientierter Laie.”3 It could be argued that this is a generally accepted opinion, though a few scholars have been rather more sympathetic to Crates’ contributions to the science of geography.4 His geographical work is an excellent example of his eclectic, but still highly selective,5 intellectual interests, and his contribution to physical allegorizing, especially in the form of the so-called sphairopoiia (“the sphericity of the cosmos”), is well recognized.6 Furthermore, his geographical teachings—their shortcomings notwithstanding—survived down to late antiquity, including his theory that the four great land masses were divided by equatorial and meridian oceans.7 Since a number of authors, among them Strabo, Geminus, and Macrobius, show significant familiarity with his works, it would not be an exaggeration to claim that both his geographical and his allegorizing teachings were well known both in antiquity and the Middle Ages (cf. Romm 1992: 130). Crates’ interpretation of the Homeric epics is usually styled as “Stoic,” but this notion is unsubstantiated (Asmis 1992: 140; Porter 1992: 85–86). It is also a regular feature of both ancient and modern criticism to charge Crates with reading either Stoic or his own idiosyncratic principles into Homer, taking his poems as cosmic allegories (Asmis 1992: 141; Porter 1992: 72; cf. Graf 1993: 194, 198). A good example of this practice is offered by Geminus of Rhodes (fl. first cent. b.c.e.), who in his Introduction to the Phenomena accuses Crates of “fabulously distorting” Homer’s descriptions (Porter 1992: 87) or simply “speaking in marvels” about them (Evans and Berggren 2006: 215) and, further, of reading his own theory of sphairopoiia into what Homer had actually said.8 A similar accusation is found in Philodemus (P.Hercul. 1676 fr. 2 = fr. 99) and Heraclitus (All. 27.2 = fr. 3). Such charges are, on the whole, 3 Abel 1974: 1052.4–5. Generally, “his reputation is not very enviable ... he is regarded as something of a crank” (Asmis 1992: 138). He is referred to as “a highly eccentric geographer-critic” by Romm 1992: 179, while Thomson 1948: 202–3 calls his Homeric geographical exegesis a “strange aberration” and his theory of oceans “hardly better than an idle fancy of misguided scholars.” 4 E.g., Aujac 1987b: 162–64. Cf. Mette 1936: xx, 66–67, 90–93; Uhden 1936: 106–15. 5 This description of Crates’ range of activities is found in Porter 1992: 87. 6 Frr. 37, 99; cf. fr. 50. For Crates’ sphairopoiia, see Mette 1936: vii–viii, xx, 11–12, 30–42, 55–58; Asmis 1992: 141; Porter 1992: 87–89; Broggiato 2001: lii, lxii, 217–18, 257. 7 Fr. 37, compare Macrob. In Somn. 2.9.1–6 (= fr. 35f Mette). See also Mette 1936: 77–78; Uhden 1936: 106. Possible representations of this theory can be found on the denarii of T. Carisius (Crawford 1983, 464.3a–c, Pl. LIV, 46 b.c.e.), L. Aemilius Buca (Crawford 1983, 480.6, Pl. LVII, 44 b.c.e.), and L. Mussidius Longus (Crawford 1983, 494.39a–b, Pl. LX, 42 b.c.e.); cf. Berger 1903: 458; Thomson 1948: 203; Aujac 1987b: 164. 8 Geminus’s work will be abbreviated hereafter as “Gemin. Elem. Astron.” For the final charge, see Asmis 1992: 141; Porter 1992: 87; Gemin. Elem. Astron. 16.27 = fr. 37. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 297 correct. Crates’ approach to Homer and his interpretative method were thus highly idiosyncratic, with his belief in the Poet’s “wide learning” allowing him to interpret Homer’s stories as “scientific hypotheses.”9 the map Given Crates’ reception and influence, it comes as no surprise that there is an ancient map based on his geographical and allegorizing teachings. It is a unique graphical representation, embodying not only his geographical conceptions, but also his allegorizing interpretation of a section of Homer’s narrative. The existence of the map supports the tradition that Crates made a model, a terrestrial globe or a sphairopoiia, “presumably as a visual analogue to his Homeric exegeses” (Porter 1992: 88).10 A version of the map was first published by Neugebauer 1975a (cf. 1975b: 735). Jacob 1988: 2 suggested that the influence of “a theory recognized by Hellenistic thinkers,” especially Crates of Mallos, concerning the four quarters of the earth, might have been at work in the making of the map, as evidenced by the presence of the antoikoumenē. He also recognized (at least) three levels of knowledge employed in the making of the map (geographical, cosmological, eschatological: Jacob 1988: 4), but did not further develop his thoughts in this direction. The map is preserved in three copies as a part of an astrological compendium and in nine further copies accompanying the anonymous scholia to Theon’s commentary on Ptolemy’s Procheiroi kanones (Edson and SavageSmith 2000: 27).11 All twelve examples show a great similarity with one another, albeit with minor differences.12 The map depicts a zonal division of Ἐπιστημονικὰς ὑποθέσεις: Strabo 3.4.4 = fr. 75; cf. Broggiato 2001: lv. Cf. Kroll 1922: 1636.34–40; Mette 1936: 60; Broggiato 2001: 284–85; see Strabo 2.5.10 (fr. 134), Gemin. Elem. Astron. 16.22 (fr. 37). In the words of Romm 1992: 189, “Crates sought to ‘map’ the Homeric poems on the enormous globe he devised to illustrate Stoic geographical theory.” 11 The following MSS contain copies of the map (list from Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 27): Berlin, Staatsbibliothek, MS Phill. 1479 (fol. 28v); Oxford, Bodleian Library, MS Barocci 94 (fol. 118v); Oxford, Bodleian Library, MS Marsh 42 (fol. 4r/156b); Florence, Biblioteca Laurenziana, Cod. gr. 28.1 (fol. 177r); Florence, Biblioteca Laurenziana, Cod. gr. 28.7 (fol. 107r); Florence, Biblioteca Laurenziana, Cod. gr. 28.12 (fol. 296v); Florence, Biblioteca Laurenziana, Cod. gr. 28.47 (fol. 271v); Venice, Biblioteca Marciana, Cod. gr. 314 (fol. 222v); Oxford, Bodleian Library, MS Canon. Gr. 32 (fol. 17r); Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale de France, fonds gr. 2390 (fol. 155v); Escorial, Bibl. Monasterio de San Lorenzo el Real, MS (Φ I 5 = gr. 183 (fol. 31v); Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica, Cod. gr. 183 (fol. 21r). 12 Neugebauer 1975, Pl. III.2; Jacob 1988: 3, Fig. 1; Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 8, Fig. 1; 9, Fig. 2; 10, Fig. 3; 11, Fig. 4. 9 10 298 Tomislav Bilić Figure 1. The Map of Crates. From Edson, E. and Savage-Smith, E. 2000. “An Astrologer’s Map: A Relic of Late Antiquity.” Imago Mundi 52: 7-29. Figure 5 (p. 12). Reproduced by kind permission of Imago Mundi Ltd. the earth’s surface and/or the heavens, together with the line of the ecliptic, a meridian connecting the poles, and several geographical terms (see Figure 1). South of the equator there is a depiction of a “fiery unnavigable sea” or the “ocean towards13 antoikoumenē.”14 This sea/ocean extends to approximately midway between the equator and the winter tropic, that is, in the sections Κατά, surely not “below,” as in Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 27, cf. 12, Fig. 5. Hiatt 2008: 42–43 simply translates “the sea of the ....” Cf. Neugebauer 1975a: 313: “Ocean of the ...” and Jacob 1988: 2 and his no. 23 on Fig. 2 (p. 3): “Océan de l’antoekoumène.” For discussion on the semantic range of κάτω, see Nicolai 1984: 103–12. 14 No. 23 on the schematic map in Neugebauer 1975a: 313, Fig. 1; Jacob 1988: 3, Fig. 2; and Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 12, Fig. 5, reproduced here as Figure 1 by kind permission of Imago Mundi Ltd. Designations of this body of water are found only on the maps in the scholia accompanying Theon’s commentary (Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 27). 13 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 299 close to the eastern and western borders of the map; approaching the central meridian, however, the coast veers from both sides tapering towards the south, traversing the winter tropic and joining the meridian approximately halfway between the tropic and the antarctic circle or circle of permanent invisibility. Within the “bay” thus formed, there is an inscription: the “sea towards15 antoikoumenē.”16 “Out of ” this sea/bay flow the “River Lethe” (no. 30) and “Pyriphlegethon River” (no. 31), running in a curved course through the temperate zone of the antoikoumenē and then flowing into the “Marsh of Acheron” (no. 32), precisely at the antarctic circle.17 The Acheron stretches in the form of a semicircle almost to the south pole.18 The equatorial sea, or, more precisely, the ocean extending between the temperate zones—a distinctive feature of Crates’ system—represents, as attested in literary sources, the “sea” that Odysseus must pass going from Aeaea to the “river ocean’s stream” and Hades, and back (Od. 12.1–4; cf. 11.1–2, 11), while said stream, “an estuary or a gulf stretching from the winter tropic (χειμερινός τροπικός) towards the South Pole (νότιος πόλος)” (fr. 57 ap. Strabo 1.1.7), is represented by “the sea (stretching) towards the antoikoumenē” on the map. This branch of the Ocean, according to both Crates’ literary exegesis and the map, divides the landmass of the southern hemisphere into two parts (Mette 1936: 75–78; Broggiato 2001: liii, 224).19 If we compare the map with Crates’ description as provided by Strabo, we see that the sea on the map stretches from approximately midway between the equator and winter tropic to halfway between the tropic and the pole, while Crates described the ἀνάχυσις or κόλπος as commencing at the tropic itself. Nonetheless, it seems that the map, at least the part representing Again κατά, this time left untranslated by Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 28. Cf. Neugebauer 1975a: 315: “Sea of the ...” and Jacob 1988: 2 and his no. 27 on Fig. 2 (p. 3): “mer de l’antoekoumène.” 16 No. 27 on the map, Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 28. 17 Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 14, 28; Hiatt 2008: 42–44; cf. Dilke 1985: 170 with Pl. 29. 18 On the map in the scholia accompanying Theon’s commentary from Oxford, Bodleian Library, MS Canon. Gr. 32, fol. 17r (Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 11, Fig. 4) the Acheron actually stretches to the very pole. On another map from the same context (Marcianus gr. 314, fol. 222v) it almost touches the pole (Neugebauer 1975a, Pl. III.2; Dilke 1985, Pl. 29; Jacob 1988: 3, Fig. 1). 19 See nos. 24–26, 28–29 on the map. Mette 1936: 76–77 presupposes the existence of another branch of Ocean stretching from the summer tropic to the north pole (the Atlantic) and a corresponding “pair” of branches at the opposite (eastern) part of the oikoumenē. The question is whether Odysseus started off from the western border of the oikoumenē—along the southern section of the “Atlantic” (so Mette)—or from the eastern, which would be more in line with Homer’s text (Aeaea in the east, Od. 12.3–4). 15 300 Tomislav Bilić the southern hemisphere, depicts Crates’ ideas of (cosmic) geography, with indisputable Hades-related toponyms placed in the southern hemisphere. the world according to crates i: the cimmerians and hades / tartarus Strabo’s description of Crates’ geography undeniably places Hades at the very south pole; this corresponds to the latter’s placing of the Cimmerians at the pole(s) as well. According to Crates (fr. 53, cf. Lehmann-Haupt 1921: 426.35–36), the Cimmerians are identical to the “Cerberians” and live at both poles,20 or solely at the south pole,21 and the meteorological characteristics of their land as described in the Odyssey correspond to those at the pole.22 In fr. 54 Crates is said to have placed Homer’s Cimmerians below the north pole; but Mette emends θερινός τροπικός (Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.17) in this fragment to the more plausible χειμερινός τροπικός.23 Crates’ symmetrical arrangement of the continents on the earth’s surface, however, could have allowed him to distribute the Cimmerians to both poles, since Homer’s description of meteorological characteristics of their country, as understood by Crates, could equally be applied to either of the two extreme points on the earth’s surface. What we know for certain is that Crates also compared (fr. 7) meteorological features under the poles with Homer’s description of Tartarus, most probably Thus Berger 1904: 15; Wrede 1937: 1971.19–21. Thus Mette 1936: 84n1, 88, 92; Broggiato 2001: xlix, liv, 222. 22 Cf. schol. HV Od. 10.86 (2.454 Dindorf) = fr. 37f Mette and Eust. Od. 10.86, i.369 Stallbaum = fr. 37g Mette, where the meteorological characteristics of the Cimmerian land are compared with, and opposed to, those that obtain among the Laestrygonians. Crates again mentions together the Cimmerians and the eternal night in Eust. Od. 11.19, i.398 Stallbaum = fr. 37k Mette. Schol. Dionys. Per. 586 (GGM 2.451–52) associates Od. 11.19 (the darkness of the Cimmerian land) and 12.4 (Helios’s risings on Aeaea) with a respective six-month day and a six-month night in the farthest north and south when the sun is in the northern and southern portions of its voyage, respectively (from the vernal to the autumnal equinox, and vice versa). But this applies only to the poles; at the arctic circles, on the other hand, the sun both rises and sets during these periods, except on the very solstices. For the Cerberians, cf. Ar. Ran. 187; schol. Ar. Ran. 187, p. 280 Firmin-Didot = fr. 38e Mette; Soph. fr. 1060 Radt = Etym. Magn. 513.45–48 s.v. Κιμμερίους = fr. 38d Mette; Lehmann-Haupt 1921: 426.24–34; see also schol. H Od. 11.14, citing Aristarchus = fr. 38f Mette and schol. PV = fr. 38a Mette; Eust. Od. 11.14, i.396.34–36 Stallbaum = fr. 38c Mette; cf. Hesych. κ 2298 s.v. κερβέριοι, Κερβερίους and Phot. Bibl. s.v. Κερβέριοι (Mette 1936: 274 on fr. 38e). Perhaps also Ephorus FGrHist 70F134b ap. [Scymn.] 239–40. 23 Crates “muß den χειμερινός τροπικός erwähnt haben” (Mette 1936: 84n1, cf. 265–66; also Abel 1974: 1054.51–66). 20 21 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 301 (given the account of Strabo) placing the latter under the south pole (Steph. Byz. s.v. Τάρταρος = Hdn. 3.1.194.29–32 s.v. Τάρταρος). A scholiast on the Iliad associates Tartarus with the “dark portion of the oikoumenē” (schol. D Il. 8.13 = fr. 39b Mette, van Thiel 2000: 296), which cannot be right, at least if we take the oikoumenē to mean the region in the northern hemisphere extending 180° (or less) in longitude, that is, “our” quarter of the earth, while another scholiast identifies ζόφον ἠερόεντα as the “dark portion of the earth,” which is more precise (schol. bT Il. 15.191 = fr. 39c Mette). Thus Crates’ idea of the southern hemisphere as it is attested in literary sources conforms to its representation on the map. the world according to crates ii: laestrygonians, draco, and the arctic circle The Cimmerians suggest the presence of another of Homer’s mythical peoples discussed by Crates, unfortunately not represented on the map: the Laestrygonians. According to Homer, the Laestrygonians achieved a certain level of civilization, as opposed to the carefree Lotophagoi and lawless Cyclopes.24 Nevertheless, they are described as giants (Od. 10.111, 120) and cannibals (10.116, 124). The name of their city (or the epithet describing it, as argued strongly by Page 1973: 34–35), Tēlepylos, translates as “distant gate.”25 The main feature of the land of the Laestrygonians, however, is the fact that here “the paths of night and day are close together” (Od. 10.86: ἐγγὺς γὰρ νυκτός τε καὶ ἤματός εἰσι κέλευθοι). This verse has been analyzed in various ways by both ancient scholiasts and modern investigators, who have often come to different conclusions in their interpretations of its significance.26 They practice cattle-breeding (implicit in Od. 10.82–85); know of fire (10.99); their land is traversed with wagon-roads (10.103–4); they live in a city (10.81–82, 104, 108, 118); and their mode of government is characterized by some kind of an assembly (10.114), a king (10.110), and a queen (10.112–15). 25 Woodbury 1966: 612; Frame 1978: 60; Käppel 2001: 18; Marinatos 2001: 403; Nakassis 2004: 225 all translate the name in similar terms (“distant,” “far-away,” “far away,” “Ferntor,” and “far gate,” respectively), while West 1997: 406–7; 2005: 62 renders it as “distant portal”; Page 1973: 35–36, who does not accept the usual translation, claims that the adjective τηλέπυλος could only mean “far-gated” (cf. Coxon 2009: 275), “if τηλε- has anything to do with distance”. 26 See, e.g., schol. Od. 10.82, 85–86 (2.452–54 Dindorf); Packard 1874: 33–34, 36–37, 39–40; Merry, Riddell, and Munro 1886–1901: 1.406–7 on X.81; Pocock 1958, 1968; Vos 1963: 18, 22–23, 25–26; Woodbury 1966: 611–12, 616; Page 1973: 42, 122n26; Heubeck and Hoekstra 1989: 48; Marinatos 2001: 396; Nakassis 2004: 224; West 2005: 47. 24 302 Tomislav Bilić Crates’ discussion of the Laestrygonians, in the form it has been transmitted, reveals his ideas on the questions of latitude, arctic circle(s), and the visibility of stars in different regions. According to one group of sources, he certainly understood the phenomenon of the change in the duration of the longest day depending on the latitude, and supposedly also the concept of the fixed arctic circle; according to another, he did not quite understand the difference between the always visible—changeable—and the fixed arctic circle. Thus, according to fr. 50 he compared the main feature of the land of the Laestrygonians with Aratus’s description of the constellation Draco (Phaen. 61–62), placing the territory “about (περί) the head of Draco,” that is, in the area directly below it.27 The head of Draco, according to Aratus, νίσσεται, ἧχί περ ἄκραι / μίσγονται δύσιές τε καὶ ἀντολαὶ ἀλλήλῃσιν, “wheels near where the limits of setting and rising blend” (Mair 1921: 211) or, in the words of other translators, “moves where the limits of rising and setting are confounded” (Evans and Berggren 2006: 5), “passes through the point where the end of settings and the start of risings blend with each other” (Kidd 1977: 77), or “goes around near the place where the limits of setting and rising mingle together.”28 This conception of Draco’s movements in Aratus is certainly derived from Eudoxus, as confirmed by Hipparchus (1.4.7–8, 32.25–34.21 Manitius = Eudoxus fr. 16 Lasserre = Attalus fr. 5 Maass). 27 Schol. HQ Od. 10.86 (2.453 Dindorf) = fr. 37e Mette; cf. schol. HV Od. 10.86 (2.454 Dindorf) = fr. 37f Mette, Eust. Od. 10.86, i.369 Stallbaum = fr. 37g Mette, and schol. Q and MDKVUA Phaen. 62 = fr. 37h Mette. “Crates supposes that the nights in Laestrygonia were short; and that the reason for this is that the people lived near [Broggiato (forthcoming; see n1): “close to”] the head of the constellation Draco, about which the astronomerpoet Aratus says [Phaen. 61–62]. Thus, because the star’s rising and setting are very close together, Homer can say [Od. X.86]” (schol. HQ Od. 10.86, translation in Page 1973: 43). We will explain shortly what “directly below” means. Page’s translation is somewhat misleading in that what Crates actually says is simply “for this reason—the proximity of risings to settings ...,” rather than the rising/setting of any particular asterism (compare the translation in Broggiato [forthcoming; see n1]: “accordingly, since the risings are close to the settings”). Only in schol. Q Phaen. 62 does Crates explicitly connect the rising(s) and setting(s) to the phenomena associated with the constellation Draco as observed from the latitude of Greece. 28 Broggiato (forthcoming; see n1). Cf. the Latin translations of Cic. Nat. D. 2.108 = Aratea fr. 10 Soubiran; German. Arat. 60–62 (compare proxima signa occasus ortusque in 61–62, a spatial reference on the rising and setting of Draco, with breuis occasus ortusque intercipit hora in 288, a temporal reference on the rising and setting of the sun); Avien. Arat. 164–68; Hyg. Poet. astr. 4.3, who cites both Aratus and Cicero and, moreover, associates Od. 10.86 with these verses (fr. 37i Mette) . Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 303 So, what did Crates mean by “about (περί) the head of Draco”? Page 1973: 43 was right in believing that Crates placed the Laestrygonians “below the head of Draco” due to the shortness of their nights, but was wrong to assume that the shortness was explained by Crates with reference to Draco’s short “star-time.” Perhaps Page was rather referring to the constellation’s short disappearance below the horizon observed from either Greece or some higher northern latitude, since Draco is anything but “a very short-lived star.” Moreover, if Crates was aware of the different visibility of stars depending on the latitude of the observer—a hypothesis we will discuss below—he would have known that a “Laestrygonian” high-latitude Draco would be completely circumpolar.29 It is therefore perhaps better to understand περὶ τὴν κεφαλὴν τοῦ δράκοντος as “(directly) below the head of Draco” in the sense of, the area “where the head of Draco is at the zenith.”30 The head of Draco is at the zenith when observed from 53°–55°24' northern latitude,31 or from 52°57'33"–58°07'16" 29 Abel 1974: 1052.3–1053.14 claims that Crates’ understanding of latitude was very limited; if he was truly unaware of the phenomenon mentioned, then Abel’s claim would be correct. But see below. 30 Cf. Page 1973: 43, who understands Crates’ words as referring to the “region immediately below” Draco. Mette 1936: 86–87, 91–92 also thinks that the expression refers to the region where the head of Draco is at the zenith, but further believes that Crates associated this region with the one in which the longest day is of 23 hours. “Directly overhead on the meridian” is usually expressed with phrases such as Aristotle’s ὑπό (thus, ὑπὸ τὴν ἀρκτόν, Mete. 2.5.362b8; Dicks 1970: 210). Geminus regularly uses the phrases “under the equator” or “under the pole” (Elem. Astron. 5.36, 38, 42, 43 [54.23–24, 56.11–13, 58.3–4, 58.11–12 Manitius], 6.23 [76.25–26 Manitius]) precisely in the meaning “directly” or “vertically under.” This also applies to the use of such expressions in Parmenides (T74 Coxon = DK 28A44a = Aët. 3.11.4), Eratosthenes, Polybius, Posidonius, and Strabo, which refer to the areas “under” the poles, tropics, and the equator (Eratosth. IIA5 Berger = fr. 45 Roller, Posid. fr. 49, 208 E-K, Polyb. 34.1.7, 16–17, Strab. 2.2.3, 3.1–3, 5.37, 43). For Eratosthenes (IIB26 Berger = fr. 44 Roller ap. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 15.3), the terrestrial equator is directly below the celestial one; Polybius, when referring to the zones “below the arctic circles” (Strabo 2.3.1–2 = Polyb. 34.1.14–15), probably has in mind the territories below the entire (ant)arctic celestial zones, as does Plutarch when referring to ὑπαρκτίων κλιμάτων (Mar. 11.4, cf. Sert. 17.3), while Ptol. Tetr. 2.2.3 generally discusses the northern peoples living under the Bears (ὑπὸ τὰς ἄρκτους), who have the constellations directly above their heads. Stob. Flor. 1.49.45 also uses the expression in a similar meaning, referring to an anthropomorphic image of the earth with feet placed in the north, as well as to the inhabitants of this northern region. 31 Using the values of Hipparchus, 1.4.8, p. 34.10–14 Manitius: the head of Draco stretches from 34°36' to 37°. The information in Cleomedes (De motu circ. 1.5.59 Todd), placing the head of Draco at the zenith for Lysimachia (c. 40°40' north latitude), is certainly erroneous, because the southernmost stars in the head (δγ Draconis, declination 52°54' in 304 Tomislav Bilić in the time of Hipparchus, and 53°15'47"–58°21'45" in the time of Eudoxus. This is much to the south of the fixed arctic circle, but is precisely on the always visible circle of Rhodes (54°), used by majority of astronomers as the arctic circle (see below). Therefore, it would seem that Crates, in associating the Laestrygonians with the constellation Draco, located them with reference to the always visible circle of Rhodes, which he took as the arctic circle. We might perhaps go a bit further than this. Neugebauer claims that the origin of the use of the latitude of 54° (= 36° from the pole) should not be sought with reference to the latitude of Rhodes, but rather associated with “a cosmologic doctrine of ‘pythagorean’ flavor” (1972: 247, cf. 1975b: 733), which carved out a quadrant of 15 parts (90°) from a circle of 60 parts (360°) and divided it up according to a “neat numerical pattern” of 4 (24°, from the equator to the tropic) : 5 (30°, from the tropic to the arctic circle) : 6 (36°, from the arctic circle to the pole). The resultant position of the arctic circle was later “translated” into the Rhodes-determined always visible circle. Whether Crates was aware of this tradition is another question, but it would certainly strengthen his cosmological argument.32 Dicks 1960: 24–25 claims that it is “very unlikely” that Eudoxus was aware of the fixed arctic circle and that he calculated his (always-visible) circle with reference to the latitude of Rhodes, placing it at 54°.33 In this Eudoxus was followed by many: thus, for example, Eratosthenes,34 Geminus,35 Manilius (Astron. 1.565–67), Hyginus (Astron. 1.6.2), Achilles Tatius (Isag. 26, 29 = 100 b.c.e.) were at least 12° further north (Tozer 1897: 169–70 and Keyser 2001: 363–65 argue for Dicaearchus as the author of this measurement). Furthermore, Cleomedes gives the head’s declination as 48° (1.5.60 Todd), which neither corresponds to his previous statement nor to the real value. 32 For Crates’ (fr. 34ab Mette) division of the sphere into five or six zones according to this pattern (6–5–4), see Mette 1936: 66–67 and Uhden 1936: 108. 33 Stevens 1980: 270 believes that Eudoxus had calculated the value for an arctic circle with reference to Knidos, which was later adopted for the latitude of Rhodes. Bianchetti 1998: 43, 153 believes that it was Pytheas who was the first to recognize the difference between the always-visible and fixed arctic circle. 34 IIB19 Berger/M1 Roller ap. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 16.6–9; IIB20 ap. Achilles Tatius, Isag. 29; IIB24/M2 ap. Macrob. In Somn. 2.6.3–5; IIB25 ap. Anonymus, Geographiae Expositio Compendiaria 1.2. But see further below. 35 Elem. Astron. 5.46, 58.21–60.2 Manitius (esp. 58.22–23), 16.7–11, 166.4–168.16 Manitius. On the other hand, Geminus is well aware of variable arctic circles (always visible circles, that is) at different latitudes (Elem. Astron. 5.47–48, 60.3–13 Manitius; 16.12, 168.16–20 Manitius). Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 305 Eratosth. II B 20), Theon (Astron. 3.42, p. 202.17–203.9 Hiller),36 Macrobius,37 and an anonymous epitomizer38 all placed the limit of the northern habitable zone at 54°, a testament to the strength of the Eudoxean tradition.39 A similar idea, it can be argued, is present in Strabo’s Geography. Strabo disagreed with Hipparchus (see below) and placed the northern limit of the inhabited world somewhat more (2.1.13) or less (2.5.6 = Eratosth. fr. 30 Roller, 2.5.9 = fr. 34 Roller) than 38,800 stadia north of the equator,40 that is, at approximately 55°25'42", which is a value still close to the “Rhodian” standard.41 Elsewhere Strabo claims that the arctic circle—which is what Homer meant by “the Bear”42—touches the earth at its northernmost inhabited point or limit, which is the same as the most northerly point on the horizon (1.1.6).43 Since we have his explicit estimate of the most northern habitable latitude, we can On the other hand, Theon is also well aware of variable arctic circles at different latitudes (Astron. 3.9, 133.6–10 Hiller). 37 In Somn. 2.6.3–6 (2.6.3–5 = Eratosth. IIB24 Berger/M2 Roller). 38 Anonymus, Geographiae Expositio Compendiaria 1.2 (GGM 2.494 [= Eratosth. IIB25 Berger]). 39 Probably also Polybius (Strabo 2.3.1–2 = Polyb. 34.1.14–15; Bianchetti 1998: 163, 185, 194). For Crates, see above. For the purpose of some of his tables, Ptolemy in the Almagest takes into account the parallels up to the limit of 54°1' (Alm. 2.8, 1.140–41 Heiberg; Berggren and Jones 2000: 18); as late as the 14th century, accounts of high northern latitudes started at the ultimum clima at 54° (Taylor 1956: 59, 65, 67). 40 8,800 stadia is the distance from the equator to the southern limit of the inhabited world (Strab. 2.1.13, 17, 2.2 [= Eratosth. IIB22 Berger, fr. 58 Roller = Posid. fr. 49 E-K], 5.6 [= fr. 30 Roller], 35 [= fr. 57 Roller]). 41 Bianchetti 1998: 156–57 calculates different values, using Strabo’s conflicting data on the northern limit of the oikoumenē, but they all fall between 54° and 56°. 42 Il. 18.487–89 (= Od. 5.273–75). Crates shares this opinion of Strabo, although he expresses it somewhat differently (F 27). See Dicks 1970: 49; Broggiato 2001: 190; and Giampaglia 1998: 507–10 for three different emendations. Dicks argues for Crates’ attempting a change of the word’s gender (οἴη to οἶος), modifying Homer’s “the Bear” (ἡ ἄρκτος) to “the arctic (circle)” (ὁ ἀρκτικός). Broggiato removes the “solely” (reading οἷ. ἡ), while Giampaglia, through his reading of P.Oxy. 2888 col. ii.9–10, keeps οἴη, but believes it refers to the position of the Bear with respect to Orion. Strabo further interprets Heraclitus’s statement (22B120 D-K) to the same effect. Kirk 1962: 289 (cf. Marcovich 2001: 337) suggests that Strabo thinks that Heraclitus’s “limits” refer to the always visible and always invisible circles, an interpretation that Berger 1903: 79 and Burnet 1920: 135n5 believe is probably right. Arist. Poet. 1461a20–21 accepts the reading “only,” but argues that it was used because the Bear is the most conspicuous constellation of those that never set (Lucas 1968: 242). 43 Cf. schol. MQDΔKVUAS Phaen. 62, where the head of Draco touches the northern horizon (the limits, ἄκρος, of the Ocean, as understood by the scholiast) at the meridian. 36 306 Tomislav Bilić presume that Strabo here speaks of the always visible circle for the latitude of Greece or, more precisely, Rhodes. Thus, he adhered to the “teoria aristotelica” (Bianchetti 1998: 163, 185, 194–95),44 that is, the “Rhodian” standard. However, this was not the only theory known to the ancients. Thus, for example, Martianus Capella unusually placed the arctic circle at 50° (8.837).45 More important is an idea present in Hipparchus: he placed the river Borysthenes 34,000 stadia north of the equator (ap. Strabo 2.1.13 = fr. 59 Dicks, cf. 2.1.17). Since he also placed the parallel of Borysthenes 3,800 stadia north of the Massalia/Byzantion parallel,46 and since he knew of an inhabited area more than 9,100 stadia north of Massalia,47 Hipparchus’s northern limit— taking into account all the available distances—was at least 38,900 to 39,500 stadia north of the equator (55°34'17" or 56°25'43"), but more probably even farther to the north.48 Ptolemy, together with Marinus of Tyre (ap. Ptol. Geog. 1.7.1),49 placed the northern limit of the oikoumenē, together with Thoulē, at 63°.50 This latitude was later accepted by Islamic authors Al-Khwārazmi, Suhrāb (Tibbetts 1992: 102, 105n69), and the anonymous author of Hudūd al-‘Ālam (2.3, 5, 4.26; Minorsky 1970: 50–51, 59), while al-Idrīsī placed the Cf. Kidd 1988: 2.742, 744–45. For Aristotle, see below. Neugebauer 1975b: 590 believes that the text should be emended to correspond to the 6–5–4 standard, which would place the limit of the arctic zone at 54°. 46 Hipparch. fr. 54, 57 Dicks ap. Strabo 2.5.8, 42. In the last reference the Borysthenes is placed 34,100 stadia from the equator, while in 2.5.41 (Hipparch. fr. 52 Dicks) Byzantion is 30,300 stadia north of the equator (in 2.1.12 = Hipparch. fr. 15 Dicks the distance is 29,800 stadia); in 2.1.12 = Hipparch. fr. 59 Dicks (cf. 2.1.16) the distance between the two is 3,700 stadia. 47 Strabo 2.1.18 = fr. 61 Dicks = Pytheas fr. 6b Mette, T 5 Roseman. 48 Hipparchus gives the altitude of the sun on the winter solstice for this region as less than 3 cubits (if we take this to mean 2 ½ cubits this implies the latitude of 61°17') and the longest day as 19 hours (61°2') (Dicks 1960: 185; Roseman 1994: 43; Bianchetti 1998: 181, giving the latter figure as 62°2'). Compared with other data reported by Strabo, where a 2° difference is evident (Dicks 1960: 185, 188; cf. Diller 1934: 266–67; Bianchetti 1998: 181), this limit was placed (by Strabo) at ca. 59°10' north (= ca. 41,400 stadia; actually, ca. 42,800 = 61°10', cf. Dicks 1960: 193). 49 Jones and Keillar 1996: 48 have tried to reconstruct Marinus’s theory from the data in Ptolemy, and claim that he placed Thoulē at ca. 69°, although Ptolemy explicitly claims that he placed it at 63°. 50 Geog. 1.20.8, 23.1 (= 1.23.22 Nobbe), 24.5, 2.3.14 (62°40'–63°15'), 3.5.1 Müller, 6.16.1, 7.5.12, 16, 6.7–8, 8.3.3 Nobbe (7.5.16 and 8.3.3 only mention the longest day of 20 hours on Thoulē). Cf. Alm. 2.6, 1.1.114.9–11 Heiberg, 29th parallel of Thoulē at 63°, also with the longest day of 20 hours; also Anon. Summaria ratio geographiae in sphaera intelligendae 2.9, 15 (GGM 2.490, 493), 63°, 20 hours. 44 45 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 307 limit somewhat to the north of 64° (Ahmad 1992: 162–63; cf. Nansen 1911: 2.203).51 Thus the Marinus/Ptolemy conception of the northern limit of the oikoumenē approaches the latitude corresponding to the fixed arctic circle, of which both authors were well aware. Others were even closer to this value. Thus Eratosthenes placed Thoulē 11,500 stadia north of the Borysthenes (II C 2 Berger = fr. 35 Roller ap. Strabo 1.4.2; cf. 1.4.4), which means 46,300 stadia north of the equator (= 66°8'34"), according to Diller 1934: 264.52 Diller arrived at this figure by taking the value for the distance from the Cinnamon-bearing country to Meroe as 3,000 stadia,53 rather than 3,400,54 and the value for the distance from Alexandria to the Hellespont as 8,000 stadia,55 rather than 8,100 (1.4.2 = II C 2 Berger, fr. 35 Roller). If we take the alternative figures, which are precisely the ones specified in the chapter where the distance to Thoulē is also given, we arrive at the figure of 46,800 stadia = 66°51'24".56 Similarly, Al-Farghānī placed the northern limit of the oikoumenē at 66° (Tibbetts 1992: 102n59), while for Hāfiz-i Abrū it was placed further to the north of 66° (Ahmad 1992: 170). In the same way, al-Dimashqi placed the northern limit on 66°10' or 66°25' (Nansen 1911: 2.212).57 Ibn Khaldoun (1377 c.e.) places it precisely at 64° (Second Prefatory Discussion of the Muqaddimah; Rosenthal 1967: 1.50, 55, 56); he also mentions the opinions of other scholars: al-Khazini (63°, 20-hours longest day), al-Khizin (10th century; 60°45', the limit of the 7th clime), and “others” (77°) (Rosenthal 1967: 1.114–15). 52 Dilke 1985: 33 and Uhden 1936: 100 have 46,400 stadia. On p. 34 Dilke has 46,300 stadia, if we take the distance from Borysthenes to Thoulē as 11,500 stadia instead of the erroneous 16,500 stadia. Bunbury 1883: 1.664 also has 46,300 stadia. If we take Eratosthenes’ acceptance of Pytheas’s placement of Thoulē on the fixed arctic circle together with the value reported for his calculation of the obliquity of the ecliptic (23°51'20", Ptol. Alm. 1.12, 67.22–68.6 Heiberg = Hipparch. fr. 41 Dicks, Eratosth. IIB42 Berger/M8 Roller, Theon, Comm. ad loc., 2.528.20–529.3 Rome = Hipparch. fr. 41 Dicks, Eratosth. IIB42 Berger/ M9 Roller; see Dicks 1960: 91), then the figure of 46,300 stadia must have represented his intended distance of Thoulē from the pole (16,700 stadia). 53 Strabo 2.2.2 = fr. 58 Roller; 5.7 = fr. 34 Roller; 35 = fr. 57 Roller; 17.3.1 = fr. 100 Roller. 54 As in Strabo 1.4.2 (= IIC2 Berger, fr. 35 Roller); Dicks 1960: 171 claims that Strabo here added 400 stadia in order to include the island of the Egyptians, the Cinnamonproducing region, and Taprobane. 55 2.1.3 = IIA2 Berger, fr. 47 Roller; 5.42 = IIC5 Berger, fr. 36 Roller. 56 Cf. Dicks 1960: 153. Bianchetti 1998: 150 takes as a starting point Pytheas’s calculation for the latitude of Massalia (43°12'17") and adds the distance from the Massalia parallel to Borysthenes (3,700/3,800 stadia) and from there to Thoulē (11,500 stadia), arriving at a latitude of “little over 64°” (actually, almost 65°). 57 He gives 63° as an alternative, though. 51 308 Tomislav Bilić The last paragraph has brought us closer to a strain in Cratetean thought concerning the problem of the arctic circle that marks his dissent from the “Rhodian” standard. Thus, again according to fr. 50, Crates compared the meteorological conditions characteristic of the land of the Laestrygonians with those obtaining in the far north—more precisely, in the area with the longest day on the summer solstice of 23 hours, and a meager one hour of night, where “the setting of the sun is near to its rising”58 and where, therefore, those that could stay awake could have earned double wages (Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.10–12, 72.2–20 Manitius).59 Consequently, the Laestrygonians would be placed somewhat to the south of the fixed arctic circle (cf. Mette 1936: 86). According to Ptolemy, however, the summer solstice day of 23 hours is located at 66° northern latitude (Alm. 2.6, 1.1.114.18–20 Heiberg),60 which Translation in Heath 1932 [1991]: 133; cf. Evans and Berggren 2006: 163: “the setting [point] draws near the rising [point]”; Broggiato (forthcoming; see n1): “the sunset is near the dawn” or “the sunset is close to sunrise.” 59 The land of the Laestrygonians is also placed on the latitude with the longest solstitial day of 23 hours by schol. P Od. 10.86 (2.454 Dindorf) = fr. 37d Mette, while Priscianus Lydus, Solutiones ad Chosroen 4, 67.9–15 Bywater = fr. 37b Mette may have compared the 23-hour longest day in the north with the situation on Thoulē (Mette 1936: 85 with n1, however, claims that all he said was that in certain areas the longest day lasts for 23 hours, while on Thoulē there is a 24-hour day, since it is on the fixed arctic circle; Mette discards as an interpolation the notion of a 5- or 6-day continuous daytime in the area where the longest day is of 23 hours). On the other hand, schol. MDΔKVUA Phaen. 62 = fr. 37h Mette (without Mette’s emendation [1936: 87 with n1, 271]); schol. Dionys. Per. 582 (GGM 2.451); Steph. Byz. s.v. Θούλη; and Eust. Dionys. Per. 581 (GGM 2.329.30–33) all mention a 20-hour longest day on Thoulē, exactly as in Ptol. Alm. 2.6 (1.1.114.9–11 Heiberg), where Thoulē, with the longest day of 20 hours, is placed at 63° north (cf. Geog. 7.5.16, 8.3.3 Nobbe for the 20-hour day at Thoulē). Qazwini’s Burdjan, a land located far to the north, with a 20-hour day and a 4-hour night (and vice versa), could refer to either the Normans or the Bulghars, and would apply equally well to both (cf. Nansen 1911: 2.210). The latitude of Thoulē (63°) and the longest day of 20 hours were facts well known to Islamic authors (Shīrazī, Ya‘qubi, Battani, Dimashqi [Nansen 1911: 2.211–12; Dunlop 1957]; cf. al-Khazini, who does not mention the island by name [Rosenthal 1967: 1.114–15], and Ulugh Beg, al-Tūsī, and al-Kāshī, who all give the latitude of Būdan/Tawā as 63° [Kennedy and Kennedy 1987: 32]); they received this information from Ptolemy (cf. a cosmological diagram in Vat. gr. 211 fol. 120r and 121v, where the 7th climate is named τούλη; Neugebauer 1975a: 316–17). According to Hyg. Poet. astr. 4.3.3 = fr. 37i Mette, the inhabitants of the region “under the head of Draco” have a night of less than a third of an hour (presumably on the summer solstice), which further associates the region with Homer’s Laestrygonians. 60 Ptolemy places the 24-hour day, thus the fixed arctic circle, at 66°08'40", 2.1.114.21– 115.7 Heiberg. 58 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 309 would place the Laestrygonians effectively on the fixed arctic circle and the northern limit of the oikoumenē according to Eratosthenes. Both the discussion in Geminus and that in Eratosthenes associate some of these concepts with the writings of Pytheas (a major source of Eratosthenes). Thus, according to Geminus, Pytheas mentions certain northern areas where “the night becomes very short ... so that, a little while after setting, the sun rises straightaway.”61 The similarity of Pytheas’s description to Homer’s was probably the reason why Crates and Geminus believed that it referred to the conditions imagined by the poet. After his mention of Pytheas, Geminus continues his paraphrase of Crates: “For indeed, since around these places62 the longest day is 23 equinoctial hours, the night lacks only one hour of being shortened to nothing, so that the setting [point] draws near the rising [point and is separated from it only] by the very short arc of the summer tropic,” glossing (still following Crates?) Od. 10.86 as “the setting [point] lies near the rising point” (fr. 50 = Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.11–12, 72.10–20 Manitius).63 This “solar” explanation certainly seems plausible enough. But the main objection to Crates’ theory in general is that he seems to have believed that Aratus’s verses (and Eudoxus’s theories behind them) refer to the risings and settings of the sun, to which Homer’s description certainly applies, while it is reasonable to assume that the Hellenistic poet is speaking instead of the risings and settings of the constellation Draco itself.64 It seems unlikely that 61 Fr. 9a Mette = fr. 8 Roseman = fr. 13a Bianchetti ap. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.9, 70.24–72.2 Manitius. Translation from Evans and Berggren 2006: 162; Roseman 1994: 140: “the night is extremely short ... so that after the setting, although only a short time has elapsed, the sun straightaway rises again,” Bianchetti 1998: 103: “la notte fosse molto corta ... cosicché a breve intervallo dal tramonto il sole sorgeva di nuovo”; Pytheas specifically mentions the regions with the longest day of 21 or 22 hours. Compare also fr. 9b Mette = fr. 9 Roseman = fr. 13b Bianchetti ap. Cosmas Indicopleustes, Topographia Christiana 2.80.6–9 Wolska-Conus. 62 Geminus refers to the region where Crates placed Homer’s Laestrygonians in 6.10 and 12, which he associates in 6.10 with northern regions described by Pytheas in 6.9. 63 Translation from Evans and Berggren 2006: 163 (compare Broggiato forthcoming; see n1). Broggiato 2001: 217–18 attributes the notion exclusively to Crates. 64 Strabo (discussing Posidon. fr. 49 E-K ap. Strabo 2.3.8, Kidd 1988: 1.268–70) similarly believes that Aratus’s “rising” and “setting” refer to the eastern and western semicircle of the horizon or the section of the sun’s path from the eastern horizon to the meridian and from the meridian to the western horizon, respectively. (The latter is most probably also the opinion of Posidonius, who interprets Homer’s “setting” as “descending from the meridian towards the horizon” [see Mette 1936: 73–74]; cf. schol. Q Phaen. 62, where it is said that the head of Draco belongs to both the eastern and western horizon, as observed from the latitude of Greece, and schol. MQDΔKVUAS Phaen. 62, where it is specified that 310 Tomislav Bilić Crates could have interpreted Aratus’s verses as applying to anything but Draco, though this is what the scholia appear to claim explicitly to be the case. Perhaps, though, what they actually assert is that Crates associated only the terms “rising” and “setting” with the diurnal path of the sun, without an explicit reference on his part to the constellation Aratus was describing. If Crates truly connected the position of the land of the Laestrygonians with the latitude of the fixed arctic circle, no matter whether he understood it as such or not, as it would seem from this second set of evidence, then this would be in direct contradiction with the first set, according to which he associated it with the always visible circle of Rhodes taken as the arctic circle. Both versions cannot be right; perhaps, after all, Crates was indeed only “at best an interested and comparatively well-oriented layman.” Then again, it seems unlikely that he understood the changeability of day length with respect to different latitudes but at the same time did not know the difference between the fixed arctic circle and the latitude-dependent always-visible circles. The introduction of Draco into the discussion may thus have been only secondary, and motivated by a cosmological doctrine demanding the neat division of the cosmic sphere.65 the semicircles of “rising” and “setting” meet at the meridian and that the head of Draco touches upon its northern intersection with the horizon; see also Kidd 1997: 200. Achilles Tatius, Isag. 35 also gives two possible explanations: Aratus either had in mind the section of the sun’s path from the eastern horizon to the meridian and from the meridian to the western horizon, or the point where the head of Draco touches upon the meridian’s northern intersection with the horizon.) This would make them meet only at the very meridian or the junction of the meridian with the horizon (cf. Strabo’s comment on the arctic circle in 1.1.6), which makes this explanation implausible. Also, Strabo, Achilles, and the scholia (perhaps also Posidonius) are referring to the sun’s diurnal path, which is only a conjecture. Similarly, Kirk 1962: 292 believes that Heraclitus’s “limits” (DK 22B120) represent the meridian. For an attempt to interpret Posidonius’s suggestion (fr. 49 E-K ap. Strabo 2.3.7–8) for “improving” Crates’ emendation (F 37, cf. fr. 34f Mette) of Homer’s description of the Aethiopians’ dwellings (Od. 1.24) by taking it as as referring to the sun’s annual path, see Kidd 1988: 1.269–70. According to this explanation, “setting” would mean the sun’s path from the summer to the winter tropic, while “rising” would mean the sun’s path from the winter to the summer tropic; “rising” and “setting” would thus meet at the solstices. Hippolytus (Haer. 4.47.4), citing Aratus, interprets the “rising” and “setting” as simply referring to the east and west, but his two hemispheres (in 4.43.8–9 the two hemispheres are the upper, consisting of pneuma and fire, and the lower, consisting of water and earth) do not make any sense in this context if they do not simply refer to an “eastern” (upper) and “western” (lower) hemisphere, thus allowing Draco to survey the entire longitudinal extension of the earth’s northern hemisphere. 65 A provisional argument for Crates’ familiarity with the concept of the fixed arctic circle can be extrapolated from the map. The inscription between the winter tropic and Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 311 There is, however, another possibility. We have mentioned already (n28) that only in schol. Q Phaen. 62 (98 Martin) is Crates explicitly said to have explained “the rising(s) and setting(s)” with the phenomena associated with the constellation Draco considered determinative of an arctic circle.66 In every other source he associates Eudoxus’s/Aratus’s “rising(s) and setting(s)” with annual solar motion.67 Thus (solar) risings and settings were somehow linked to the fixed arctic circle and the limit of the sun’s annual northern passage at c. 66° northern latitude. We hear of the sun’s “proper limits” already in Heraclitus of Ephesus,68 which is certainly an allusion to the solstices (Lebedev 1989: 43; cf. Kirk 1962: 285; Kahn 1979: 109, 156, 160, 199).69 Elsewhere the philosopher describes the Bear as “forming the limits of morning and evening” (DK 22B120 ap. Strabo 1.1.6),70 which seems to suggest that for Heraclitus the the antarctic circle states that the extension of this zone is 40 stadia in latitude (no. 28). It is possible that this figure refers to degrees; moreover, it has been suggested that the word γῆ (no. 29), appended to no. 28, actually represents a misinterpretation of a copyist and that we should read “μγ” (i.e., 43) instead (Edson and Savage-Smith 2000: 14–15). This would present us with a division of a quarter of the globe with the proportions 23°51'/24° – 43° (lat. 66°51'/67°) – 23°09'/23°. This is only one of many proposed suggestions, and it is a tentative one, to say the least. 66 This is an exceptional report of Crates’ exact words, as the anonymous reviewer points out to me, and thus deserves to be cited: ἡ τοῦ Δράκοντος κεφαλή, ἐπὶ τοῦ ἀρκτικοῦ κατεστηριγμένη κύκλου, ὃν συμβέβηκεν ἀειφανῆ εἶναι κατὰ τὴν περιαγωγὴν τοῦ οὐρανοῦ, περιαγίνεται ἐπ’ αὐτὸν τὸν ὁρίζοντα κτλ. Cf. the translation of Broggiato (forthcoming; see n1): the head of Draco is “placed on the arctic circle, that is always visible in the rotation of the sky, turns about on the horizon itself ” etc. Crates’ actual explanation of the association of Aratus and Homer is rather unconvincing (cf. schol. MDΔKVUA Phaen. 62, 100 Martin). 67 Schol. HQ Od. 10.86; schol. HV Od. 10.86; Eust. Od. 10.86, i.369; schol. MDKVUA Phaen. 62; Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.10–12. A similar conclusion of Posidonius, Strabo, Achilles, and some of the scholiasts on Aratus referred to above could have originated with Crates. 68 P.Derv. 4.8: τοὺ[ς ὅρους] – [ὅ]ρους ἑ[αυτοῦ] or ε[ἱμαρμένους] (see Lebedev 1989: 39, 46–47; Schönbeck 1993: 8, 17–20; Janko 2002: 8–9; Kouremenos, Parássoglou, and Tsantsanoglou 2006: 68–69, 130); in a corresponding passage Plutarch (De. exil. 604A = DK 22B94) has the term μέτρα (in the meaning of “limits,” cf. Seaford 1994: 286), while in De Is. et Os. 370D he retains ὅρους. 69 Cf. Diogenes of Apollonia (DK 64B3 ap. Simpl. in Phys. 1.4.187a12, Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 9.152.13–14 Diels), who also mentions the μέτρα of winter and summer as well as night and day. 70 Τέρμα (pl. τέρματα) has a double meaning: “turning post,” “turning point” (which is the only meaning present in the Iliad), but also “boundary,” “endpoint,” terminus (Kahn 1979: 51, 161; Purves 2010: 56 with n88). Strabo here believes that Heraclitus employed the term “the Bear” for the “arctic (always visible) circle.” 312 Tomislav Bilić arctic circle was defined by the Ursa Major constellation.71 Aristotle likewise associates the northern uninhabitable zone with the Bear (Mete. 362b9),72 and he also defines the boundary of the northern temperate zone as the alwaysvisible circle, presumably that for the latitude of Greece (Mete. 362b3).73 Thus the Bear might have designated the limit of the temperate zone. Much later, Ptolemy defined the limit of the northern temperate zone as “the Bears” (Tetr. 2.2.6), and two passages in Avienius suggest the connection of the Ursa Major constellation with the limits of the annual solar movement.74 It is possible that Nonnus’s northern turning-point beside which the Bears move also defines the northern limit of the sun’s annual passage.75 Hecateus of Abdera’s northern island of Helixoia76 suggests both the association with Helikē, that is, Ursa Major, and the verb ἑλίσσω, “to turn round or about” (Macurdy 1920: 140–41; Thomson 1948: 403), perhaps designating the sun’s annual turning around a solstitial turning-post associated with Ursa Major.77 Although we cannot be sure whether either Heraclitus or Hecateus associated the Bear with the fixed arctic circle, it does not seem probable (although it is certainly not impossible) Kahn 1979: 51, 162 believes that the οὖρος opposite the ἄρκτος represents Arcturus (Ἀρκτ-οῦρος) (cf. 1964: 197; Marcovich 2001: 338; McKirahan 2010: 121n28) and that the τέρματα represent its limits of morning and evening, that is, its heliacal and acronychal rising (cf. Hes. Op. 566–67, 610). Marcovich 2001: 338 suggests Draco as a candidate. 72 Cf. Aeschin. In Ctes. 165, where “the Bear” is associated with the extent of the oikoumenē. 73 In Arist. [Pr.] 26.15.942a4 the “regions of the Bear” are said to be “outside the solstice” (942a1), that is, the northern tropic. In Mete. 1.13.350b6–7 Aristotle places the Rhipaean Mountains “under the Bear” (ὑπ’ αὐτὴν δὲ τὴν ἄρκτον; cf. Hippoc. Aer. 19 for the region “under the Bears” [ὑπ’ αὐτῇσι τῇσιν ἄρκτοισι] associated with the Rhipaean Mountains), which is understood by Kiessling 1914: 850.56–58, 851.20–24, 852.22–34 as referring to the fixed arctic circle (cf. the restoration of Aesch. fr. 102 Mette ap. schol. Soph. OC 1248, 53 de Marco, where the Rhipaeans are associated with Helios’s father Hyperion; Diggle 1970: 27–28; Bridgman 2005: 44). 74 Or. mar. 649–50 (Murphy 1977: 42–43, mentioning “the limits of the Bear”) and Descr. orb. terr. 761–63 (GGM 2.184), here associated with the summer solstice’s 24-hour day at Thoulē. 75 Dion. 38.406–7, 25.398 (perhaps referring to the constellation’s lower culmination, rather than the solstice); cf. 1.454 (cf. 6.236–37), 38.284–85. 76 FGrHist 264F11a = DK 73B1 ap. Steph. Byz. s.v. Ἑλίξοια; cf. Hdn. 3.1.281 Lentz. 77 Hecateus’s Hyperborean (is)land and its association with the solstices are perhaps paralleled in HN 4.12.89, where cardines mundi are placed in the land of the Hyperboreans, together with limits (extremi) of the movements of the stars. Ferrari 2008: 145–46 with n64 believes that these cardines represent the solstice(s), as cardine Phoebus certainly does in Avienius (Arat. 653–54), but it is more probable that Pliny had the polar axis in mind here. 71 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 313 that they associated the turning of the sun with the latitude of 54° north; it is more probable to suppose that they—or at least Heraclitus—associated it with the latitude of the fixed arctic circle, even if they did not actually project it onto the terrestrial globe.78 Perhaps Eudoxus originally described the risings and settings of the sun, but he—or Aratus—associated them with the latitude of 54° north, the latitude of the Draco-determined always visible circle, in which they were followed by Crates (for this possible mistake, see below). If we analyze the ideas appearing in the various authors discussed above, it is immediately obvious that they have much in common. They all probably concern the same phenomenon, manifested on various levels: the solstice. It can be elaborated in various ways: the extreme points of the sun’s risings and settings on the horizon; its maximum distance from the equator; the longest or shortest day of the year; the increase in the length of day during the summer and decrease during winter in higher latitudes, with a 24-hour day/night at ca. 66°; etc. This maximum declination of the sun can also be defined with its position respective to the sphere of the fixed stars, in particular, circumpolar constellations such as Ursa Major and Draco. The latter were not used by Homer in connection with solar motion, but from Heraclitus onwards it was a normal practice to do so. Thus Homer (it could be argued) addressed the concept of the solstice in the Laestrygonian episode with reference to the increasing length of summer days in high latitudes and the almost 24-hour daylight on the summer solstice near the fixed arctic circle, while Heraclitus, on the other hand, focused on the association of the maximum declination of the sun respective to the circumpolar constellation of Ursa Major. Eudoxus/ Aratus introduced another circumpolar constellation into the discussion, and it was Crates who finally incorporated all these models into one, albeit arbitrarily and incoherently. This state of affairs is illustrated in Table 1. the world according to pytheas: thoulē The advent of Pytheas into the discussion raises the problem of the location of the island of Thoulē, which he introduced into Greek literature.79 Both Strabo80 and Pliny81 report Pytheas’s account of Thoulē as located a six days’ Marcovich 2001: 338 suggests that Heraclitus had the phenomenon of the midnight sun in mind when he described the limits beyond which there is no distinction between the rising and setting of the sun in DK 22B120. 79 For an overview of Pytheas, see Gisinger 1963; Whitaker 1981/82; Roseman 1994; Bianchetti 1998; and Roller 2006: 57–91. 80 1.4.2 = fr. 6a Mette = fr. 2 Roseman = Eratosth. IIC2 Berger, fr. 35 Roller. 81 HN 2.77.187 = fr. 13a Mette, T 18a Roseman. 78 314 Tomislav Bilić Table 1. Homer Heraclitus (Od. 10.86) (DK 22B94, 120) Eudoxus/Aratus (fr. 16 Lasserre/ Phaen. 61–62) Crates (fr. 50) κέλευθοι τέρματα (μέτρα, ὅροι) ἄκραι — νύξ ἑσπέρα δύσεις δύσις/ δύσεις ἦμαρ ἠώς ἀντολαί ἀνατολή/ ἀνατολαί sun, 66°? sun/Ursa Major, 66° sun?/Draco, 54 or 66° sun/Draco?, 54 or 66° sail to the north of Britain.82 Pytheas is responsible also for another notion concerning Thoulē, namely, that there the summer tropic and arctic circle become one.83 The description of a 24-hour day on the summer solstice in Cf. Bede, De temporum ratione 31, citing Pliny (Migne PL 90.434), and Adam of Bremen, Descriptio insularum aquilonis (4.)35 (Waitz 1876: 184), citing Bede; also Ranulph Higden, Polychronicon 1.31 (1.324 Babington). Solin. 23 (182, 184 Agnant) mentions a five days and nights’ sail from the Orcades, but does not mention Pytheas as his source (the total duration of the voyage from Cape Calydon to Thoulē adds up to fourteen days). Mommsen did not print this section in his edition of Solinus, considering it a much later interpolation, although it appears in some MSS (Mommsen’s edition 22.9, 1895: 101–2, where he prints only the information on the solstice above Thoulē; printed as an appendix, 1895: 219, cf. xci). Schol. 147 Descript. ins. aquil. (4.)35 (Waitz 1876: 183) mentions a nine days’ sail. Timaeus (FGrHist 566F74 ap. HN 4.16.104 = Pyth. fr. 11b Mette, T 23 Roseman) mentions another island, Mictis, a six days’ sail from Britain, which is probably a confusion with Thoulē (Müllenhoff 1870: 1.385, 472; Thomson 1948: 146n1; Cary and Warmington 1963: 256n47; Bianchetti 1998: 147, 173; Roller 2006: 72, 73n139). Romm 1992: 204n69 suggests that Plutarch probably had Pytheas in mind when he placed his Ogygia a five days’ sail (to the west) from Britain (De fac. 941A). 83 Fr. 6c Mette = fr. 6 Roseman ap. Strabo 2.5.8 = Eratosth. fr. 34 Roller. Cf. Cleomedes, De motu circ. 1.4.208–10 Todd = fr. 14 Mette, T 27 Roseman, also 1.4.222 Todd; see also Strabo 2.5.43 (Pytheas T 10 Roseman), Priscianus Lydus, Solutiones ad Chosroen 4, 67.13–15 Bywater = Crates fr. 37b Mette, Mette 1936: 268.5–7. It was Theodosius of Bithynia (2nd half of the 2nd century b.c.e.) who proved geometrically that at the distance of 66° from the equator—that is, on the fixed arctic circle—the sun does not set on the solstice or, in other words, that an observer situated at the latitude where the summer tropic is the same as the always-visible circle is actually situated on the fixed arctic circle (Aujac 1987b: 168; cf. Theodosius, De habitationibus 12, where he actually claims that 82 Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 315 Geminus84 immediately follows Pytheas’s account of a 21- or 22-hour day,85 and is probably derived from his writings, although Geminus does not explicitly mention Thoulē. We have already seen how the scholiast on Homer associated the location of the land of Laestrygonians with a latitude with the longest day of 23 hours.86 We have also seen that Priscianus Lydus (Solutiones ad Chosroen 4, 67.9–15 Bywater = Crates fr. 37b Mette) may have compared the 23-hour day in the north to the situation on Thoulē (although this seems highly unlikely: see Mette 1936: 85 with n1), while the scholiast on Aratus (schol. MDΔKVUA Phaen. 62 = fr. 37h Mette),87 among others,88 associated the 20-hour longest day with the island, and Hyginus associated the region under the head of Draco with a shortest night of less than a third of an hour with the Laestrygonians (Poet. astr. 4.3.3 = Crates fr. 37i Mette).89 The idea of a 24-hour solstitial day at Thoulē became something of a commonplace in geographical descriptions of the north. Thus according to Pliny, there is no night on the summer solstice on Thoulē, when the sun passes through Cancer, while on the winter solstice there is no day.90 Pomponius Mela generally dethe day at the summer solstice is 30 days long, since he takes the “day” to comprise the interval between the positions of the sun 15° before and after the solstice; Neugebauer 1975b: 757). Euclid, Pytheas’s contemporary, had already analyzed the risings and settings of fixed stars on the ecliptic with respect to whether they are observed from a latitude of more than, equal to, or less than 90°-ε, discussing the relation of the ecliptic to the arctic (always visible) circles at respective latitudes (Phaen. 4–7; Neugebauer 1975b: 767). 84 Elem. Astron. 6.13, 72.21–24 Manitius. Cf. 5.21, 50.3–7 Manitius; 32, 54.7–11 Manitius; 38, 56.7–13 Manitius. 85 Fr. 9a Mette = fr. 8 Roseman ap. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.9, 70.21–72.2 Manitius, cf. 10–12, 72.2–20 Manitius. Mette’s fr. 9a (1952: 28) does not include the day-lengths, since those were probably supplied by Geminus himself (see the discussion in Roseman 1994: 140, 142–43). 86 Schol. P Od. 10.86, Dindorf 1855: 2.454 = Crates fr. 37d Mette. 87 Mette (1936: 87 with n1, 271) emended the numbers in this scholion (“κ” to “κγ” and “Δ” to “Α”), thus arriving at the same relation (23:1) as that found in Geminus, but this is unnecessary. 88 Schol. Dionys. Per. 582 (GGM 2.451), Steph. Byz. s.v. Θούλη, and Eust. Dionys. Per. 581 (GGM 2.329.30–33). 89 With the emendation of unaquaque to brevissima (Mette 1936: 87, 272). 90 HN 4.16.104 = Pytheas fr. 11b Mette, T 23 Roseman. Cited by Bede, De temp. rat. 31 (Migne PL 90.436–37), in his turn cited by Adam of Bremen, Descript. ins. aquil. (4.)35 (Waitz 1876: 183). For a different theory of a six-month day on Thoulē, probably the result of a misunderstanding, see HN 2.77.186–87 = fr. 13a Mette, T 18a Roseman (cited by Bede, De temp. rat. 31 [Migne PL 90.433–34], in his turn cited by Adam of Bremen, Descript. ins. aquil. (4.)35 [Waitz 1876: 183–84]), 6.39.219 (cited by Bede, De natura rerum 47 [Migne PL 316 Tomislav Bilić scribes how the sun on the summer solstice shows its brilliance and most of its physical body as observed from the island, thus completely eliminating the night (3.6.57), while Solinus (22.9) and Martianus Capella (6.666) simply copy Pliny’s report.91 According to Cleomedes, at Thoulē when the sun is in Cancer, the day lasts a month, or less, depending on the visibility of the sign.92 Achilles Tatius reports that the sun does not set for eight(y) days in the regions beyond Thoulē (Isagoge 35, 71 Maass). The notion also appears in poetry: Statius associated the “weary sun” with Thyle, which blocks the western waves (Silv. 5.2.54–55), while Dionysius Periegetes and his Latin translators vaguely describe a nightless summer solstice day on the island.93 As we have already seen, this notion of Thoulē was sometimes misunderstood: thus Isidore of Seville, basing his report on that of Solinus, after recounting how the island received its name on account of the fact that the sun “makes” the summer solstice there, claims that there is no light beyond it.94 Bede, as we have already 90.273A]), and Mart. Cap. 6.595 (= Pytheas T 18b Roseman; cf. 608–9), as well as 4.16.104 = Pytheas fr. 11b Mette, T 23 Roseman, where Pliny reports two different theories (cited by Bede, De temp. rat. 31 [Migne PL 90.436–37], in his turn cited by Adam of Bremen, Descript. ins. aquil. (4.)35 [Waitz 1876: 183]). The misunderstanding is also present in Ranulph Higden, Polychronicon 1.31 (1.324 Babington), Honorius Augustodunensis, De imagine mundi 1.31 (Migne PL 172.130BC), Gervase of Tilbury, Otia imperialia 2.11 (Banks and Binns 2002: 326–27), and the Byzantine mid-15th-century scholar Laskaris Kananos (Lundström 1902: 16; Blomqvist 2002: 47). Compare also Antonius Diogenes (ap. Phot. Bibl. cod. 166, 110b42–111a3) for a six-month night “beyond Thoulē” (Crates fr. 37c Mette). The theory is criticized by Dicuil, De mensura 7.13 (Tierney 1967: 74–75), Priscianus Lydus, Solutiones ad Chosren 4, 67.15–17 Bywater = Crates fr. 37b Mette, and Eust. Dionys. Per. 581 (GGM 2.329.22–29). It is possible that the pythoras or pyt(h)agoras of the MSS of Martianus Capella’s work who “has disclosed what conditions are like in those regions” (Mart. Cap. 6.609 = Pytheas T 29 Roseman = fr. 12b Bianchetti)—i.e, the terrestrial poles, where days and nights are of a six months’ duration (6.608)—actually represents Pytheas (thus Stahl and Burge 1977: 227; Roseman 1994: 111–13; Bianchetti 1998: 188–89; Keyser 2001: 362; Roller 2006: 91; but see Burkert 1972: 306n36). 91 Serv. Dan. G. 1.30 does the same, claiming that there is no night at Thyle when the Sun is in Cancer. Cf. schol. Juv. 15.112 (no night on the summer solstice, no day at the winter). 92 De motu circ. 1.4.210–12 Todd = fr. 14 Mette, T 27 Roseman. 93 Dionys. Per. 580–83 (GGM 2.141); Prisc. Dionys. Per. 588–91 (GGM 2.195); Festus Avienius, Descr. orb. ter. 760–63 (GGM 2.184). Compare Eust. Dionys. Per. 581, who mentions the continuous day on the island when the sun is in Cancer (GGM 2.329.18–21), although he criticizes the notion (2.329.21–22). 94 Etym. 14.6.4; also cited by the anonymous Eulogium Historiarum 4.156 (2.113 Haydon); Ranulph Higden, Polychronicon 1.31 (1.324 Babington) cites the fact that the island received its name “because of the sun,” but does not attribute the notion to Isidore. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 317 seen, several times refers to Thoulē,95 and it is occasionally mentioned by other medieval authors.96 During the Middle Ages, the notion of “the island of the solstice” was sometimes transferred to Iceland.97 Several similar testimonies are perhaps derived from a related idea. Thus Procopius describes how in Scandinavia—called Thoulē in this section of his work—the sun is continuously present during the 40 days about the summer solstice, while it is absent for the same amount of time about the winter (Bell. 6.15.6–7). Jordanes repeats the same information about the 40-day daytime and darkness about the solstices (actually, he mentions mid-summer and winter),98 but associates the phenomenon with the Adogit people, who live in the northern part of Scandinavia (Get. 3.19–20). A very similar description of a 40-day night with the sun in Capricorn and a 40-day daylight with the sun in Cancer is found in Tzetzes (Chiliades 12.844–48, 474 Kiessling), who further associates this region with the Cimmerians (841–43). Paul the Deacon similarly describes a tribe named Scritobini, which is placed by him near the farthest limits of Germania to the northwest (Historia Langobardum 1.4–5), where for several days about the summer solstice there is a clear light during night-time, while about the winter solstice the sun is not seen at all, although there is some light (1.5). Adam of Bremen reports that in Halagland De natura rerum 9 (Migne PL 90.204A; an interpretation, it seems, similar to Isidore’s concerning the eternal darkness); In Regum librum XXX quaestiones 25 (Migne PL 91.732B;Trent Foley and Holder 1999: 129–30; Wooding 2000: 241–42; on Thyle [Iceland?] the Sun does not set about the summer solstice); De temporum ratione 31 (Migne PL 90.434–37), where he cites Solinus (22.9) and Pliny (both HN 2.186–87 and 4.104) (Roseman 1994: 78; McCready 1996: 115). 96 E.g., Adam of Bremen, Descript. ins. aquil. (4.)35 (Waitz 1876: 183–84), where he cites Bede, De temp. rat. 31; also schol. 146 on (4.)35 (Waitz 1876: 183); Giraldus Cambrensis, Topographia Hiberniae 1.17 (citing Solin. 22.9, Isid. Etym. 14.6.4, and Oros. 1.2.79; Giraldus is further cited by Petrarch, Fam. 3.1.8); Geoffrey of Monmouth, Vita Merlini 655–60. The longest day and shortest night on Tille when the sun is in Cancer, and the longest night and shortest day when it is in Capricorn, together with the fact that there is no difference nor distance between rising and setting (of the sun), are also mentioned by the 11th-century Assaph Hebraeus (Neubauer 1864: 672–73; Nansen 1911: 2.200n2). 97 E.g., in Honorius Augustodunensis, De imagine mundi 1.31 (Migne PL 172.130B), who refers to the island Isole; cf. Dicuil, De mensura orbis terrae 7.11–13 (Tierney 1967: 74–75, cited in Wooding 2000: 241 and Roseman 1994: 157n18); in 7.7–10 (Tierney 1967: 74–75) Dicuil cites Pliny (HN 2.77.187), Isidore (Etym. 14.6.4), Priscianus (Perieg. 588–91), and Solinus (22.9). Cf. also Adam of Bremen, who identified “Thyle” with “Icelan(d),” Descript. ins. aquil. (4.)35 (Waitz 1876: 184–85; cf. Parroni 1984: 356), as did Laskaris Kananos (Lundström 1902: 16; Blomqvist 2002: 47). 98 Cf. Bilić 2012. 95 318 Tomislav Bilić (northern Norway) the continuous day about the summer solstice lasts for 14 days, and the continuous night in winter 14 days (Descriptio insularum aquilonis [4.]37 [Waitz 1876: 185]).99 These unusual accounts can be compared with Polybius’s description of the sun’s behavior around its turning-points, slowing down in approaching the tropics and remaining near them for about 40 days (34.1.9 ap. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 16.34–35, 178.6–15 Manitius).100 This means that to an observer it seems as if the sun “slows down” when nearing a solstice, and that it slowly regains its “equinoctial” speed after the turn, appearing as if it “stands still” for a few days about the solstice; this period Polybius approximates to 40 days.101 The sun’s “residing” in the far north about the summer solstice could have inspired the theory found in Procopius, Jordanes, and Tzetzes, although Polybius had the area directly “below” the tropics in mind, rather than the area below the arctic and antarctic circles.102 Caesar mentions some unnamed islands around Britain, of which it is written that at the winter solstice the night there lasts for 30 consecutive days (B Gall. 5.13.3), while Plutarch describes an island named Ogygia, situated a five days’ sail west of Britain “near the place103 of the summer sunset,” where the sun sets “for less than one hour for thirty days in succession” (De fac. 941A, D). Strangely, Posidonius posits two narrow zones directly below the tropics, scorched by the sun (fr. 49 E-K ap. Strabo 2.2.3–3.1.2).104 While only Procopius explicitly connects the scenario of a multi-day daytime with Thoulē, having Scandinavia in mind, and much 99 Perhaps a mistake for 40 (Nansen 1911: 1.194n2). Cf. the anonymous Eulogium historiarum 4.92 (2.79 Haydon) and Ranulph Higden, Polychronicon 1.31 (1.326 Babington), where it is described how in northern parts of Norway the sun does not set for “many” days about the summer solstice and does not rise for “many” days about the winter solstice. Laskaris Kananos claims that at Bergen the uninterrupted daylight lasts from 24 June to 25 July (Lundström 1902: 15; Blomqvist 2002: 46). 100 Cf. a similar description, but without the exact number of days, in Cleomedes, De motu circ. 1.4.35–40, 90–92, 114–15 Todd. 101 Cf. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 6.29–32, 34–35, 38 (78.25–80.12, 80.18–82.1, 82.7–14 Manitius), 17.28 (190.23–192.3 Manitius). 102 Polyb. 34.1.7–13 ap. Gemin. Elem. Astron. 16.32–38 (176.20–178.28 Manitius). Cf. Pliny, HN 2.13.66, who claims that only the part of the earth that lies beneath (subiaceo) the zodiac is actually habitable, while the rest towards the poles is barren (squaleo), certainly taking antarctic and arctic circles as the boundary lines, not the tropics. 103 Thus Romm 1992: 204; Cherniss and Helmbold 1957: 181: “in the general direction.” 104 Cf. [Hippoc.] De victu 2.38, where it is said that the sun absorbs the moisture of the south wind when it blows “through the approaches (ἔφοδοι) of the sun under the south (ὑπὸ τὴν μεσημβρίην),” which probably refers to the tropic of Capricorn. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 319 later Tzetzes makes a “mythological” reference to the Cimmerians, both Caesar and Plutarch associate the idea with Britain, which suggests, in the light of Pytheas’s voyage and report, a link with Thoulē as well. pytheas and homer We can conclude that the location of Thoulē was bound up—from the time of Pytheas onwards—with the concept of the τροπαὶ ἠελίοιο (Od. 15.404),105 or was itself considered to lie at the sun’s very turning-place, thus earning the name of the “island of the solstice.”106 Moreover, Pytheas’s report suggests that in his account he combined the actual voyage to whatever place in the “far north” he had visited with a specific Homeric reference. An island of the solstice situated a six days’ sail to the north of Britain conforms well with Homer’s account in the Odyssey: there we find Aeolus’s floating island, situated a six days’ sail from Tēlepylus (Od. 10.80–81)107—where the paths of night and day are close together—and thus of a similar character to the island of Syriē, where the τροπαὶ ἠελίοιο are located (Od. 15.404).108 Of course, Homer does not in any way connect Syriē with the land of the Laestrygonians, but two pieces of mytho-geographical lore associated with these two locations seem to belong to a similar tradition concerned with meteorological conditions in the far north, or more precisely, on the fixed arctic circle. Hence it seems conceivable that Pytheas was not only a great explorer but perhaps also a fine Homeric scholar. Aujac 1987a: 151 believes that it is probable “that Pytheas indicated the height of the sun at the winter solstice for various latitudes not through observation, but by calculation with the help of geometry.”109 Cf. Bilić 2012. Cf. Isid. Etym. 14.6.4. Thoulē is rather explicitly associated with the concept of the sun’s turning in the poem of Dionysius Periegetes (584–86 [GGM 2.141], cf. Festus Avienius, Descr. orb. terr. 764–67 [GGM 2.184]; Eust. Dionys. Per. 581 [GGM 2.329.33–37]). 107 With this concept compare similar descriptions in Hes. Theog. 748–49 and Parmenides, 28B1.11 D-K ap. Sext. Emp. Math. 7.3 (Bowra 1937: 103; Morrison 1955: 59; Havelock 1958: 139, 1978: 270; Dolin 1962: 96; Vos 1963: 28, 34; Guthrie 1965: 12; Stokes 1963: 11n3; West 1966: 367; Woodbury 1966: 611; Frame 1978: 60; Ferrari Pinney and Sismondo Ridgway 1981: 142; Kirk, Raven, and Schofield 1983: 243–44; Ballabriga 1986: 125–26; Freeman 1996: 41; Marinatos 2001: 396; Steele 2002: 583–84; Morgan 2000: 76–77; Mourelatos 2008: 15; Coxon 2009: 9, 51, 275–76). 108 See the preceding discussion on the 40-day period of daytime/night when the sun travels near the tropics. Cf. Bilić 2012. 109 Cf. Carpenter 1973: 176, 191–92 (also cited in Whitaker 1981/82: 160), who claims further that Pytheas derived his values for the length of daylight at various latitudes from 105 106 320 Tomislav Bilić He knew beforehand, by studying the geometry of the sphere, of a latitude “where, at the summer solstice, the day lasted twenty-four hours and the sun did not disappear under the horizon. He located the island of Thule on this particular circle.”110 Aujac continues by stating that “he [Pytheas] may have undertaken his voyage to the northern seas partly in order to verify what geometry (or experiments with three-dimensional models) had taught him.” Several other authors share this opinion. Thus Bianchetti 1998: 45, 155, 181 believes that Pytheas’s observations actually empirically verified Eudoxus’s theoretical exposition of the celestial phenomena—especially the behavior of the sun—in high latitudes.111 Similarly, Dilke 1985: 29–30 (further cited in Roller 2006: 63n52) suggests that the main object of Pytheas’s voyage was to obtain the latitudes for the far north, while Heidel 1937: 108 believes that his objective was to gather evidence confirming the sphericity of the earth. Similarly, Roseman 1994: 145 claims that it is “the concept of a spherical earth” Pytheas “is most likely to have set out to demonstrate,” since in his time it “was still a theory needing the kinds of data he brought back for its confirmation,”112 while Thomson 1948: 153 maintains he was aware that he was “testing the zone theory.” Dicks 1960: 187 believes that he “combined trade with scientific exploration,”113 and according to Roseman 1994: 148, cf. 155, he was a physical scientist (physikos, philosophos; for the latter, cf. Käppel 2001: 11). It has further been claimed that he was the first to recognize the difference between the always-visible and the fixed arctic circle (Bianchetti 1998: calculation—after he had ascertained the latitude through different means—rather than observation. It is probable that he determined the latitudes by observing the elevation of the pole (Nansen 1911: 1.46–48; this was one of Hipparchus’s procedures, Ptol. Geog. 1.4; Neugebauer 1975b: 938 also argues for the primacy of other means, rather than the longest daylight, of determining geographical coordinates of a locality, namely, observations used to determine latitude). 110 Cf. Dilke 1985: 30; Bianchetti 1998: 191. This was already anticipated by Bunbury 1883: 1.614. 111 Cf. Diller 1975: 225, also cited in Roller 2006: 74, where Eudoxus is said to have inspired Pytheas, and Müllenhoff 1870: 1.234–35; cf. Berger 1903: 336; Heidel 1937: 99n212, 108; Bianchetti 1998: 37, where it is suggested that Pytheas was a pupil of Eudoxus. 112 Cf. Bianchetti 1998: 188, who claims that Pytheas empirically demonstrated the sphericity of the earth. 113 For his dual—scientific and mercantile—motivation, see Bianchetti 1998: 65. Compare also Müllenhoff 1870: 1.312; Tozer 1897: 154; Holmes 1907: 220 (also cited in Whitaker 1981/82: 163n90); Nansen 1911: 1.45; Walbank 1948: 173 (= 2002: 45) (erroneously cited in Whitaker 1981/82: 162); Thomson 1948: 143; Cunliffe 2002: 154; and Roller 2006: 63, 74, all of whom emphasize Pytheas’s scientific motives in undertaking his voyage. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 321 43, 153).114 Thus Aujac and others believe that Pytheas’s voyage was partly motivated by the wish to gather specific scientific data, while asserting that his data on the altitude of the solstitial sun came through calculation and that he knew of a “Thoulē” before the voyage itself even commenced. This indeed makes the voyage, in terms of theoretical background, superfluous, especially if we take into account the Homeric parallels schematically listed below. Thus Pytheas’s voyage was only an empirical confirmation of certain geometrical postulates; he empirically tested the theories concerning the phenomena in high northern latitudes that had already been theoretically predicted by the astronomers,115 combining his actual experience with specific Homeric reference(s) (see Table 2). Table 2. Pytheas Britain Homer Aeolus’s island six days’ sail to the north six days’ sail (unspecified direction) Thoulē: perpetual day on the summer solstice the island of the sun’s turning Tēlepylos: the paths of night and day are close together (Syriē) τροπαὶ ἠελίοιο Crates 54 or 66° N Aeaea 66° S, winter tropic Hades, the Cimmerians south pole For his scientific achievements, see also Bianchetti 1998: 45–46 and Käppel 2001: 11. Compare what Deinias has to say in Antonius Diogenes’s Wonders beyond Thoulē: “Deinias claimed here [beyond Thoulē] to have seen what the devotees of astronomy speculate about, for instance that there are some men who live beneath the Great Bear, and that the night can be a month long, or more or less, or even six months, or even a year.” (Phot. Bibl. 166.110b39–111a2; translation in Romm 1992: 209). Thus Deinias “empirically” tested the theories concerning the phenomena in high northern latitudes that had already been theoretically predicted by the astronomers, which echoes what Pytheas probably also did. 114 115 322 Tomislav Bilić If Homeric descriptions are thus an important part of Pytheas’s worldview, this would also account for the latter’s similarities with Crates’ account, given that both focus on the exact same data. It is fundamentally Homeric exegesis that we see lurking behind both Pytheas’s and, especially, Crates’ models, which is not unusual if we take into account the reputation Homer enjoyed during both the Classical and the Hellenistic periods as a true authority in questions of geography—including mathematical geography. In a way Pytheas actually followed in Odysseus’s footsteps, visiting or claiming to have visited a “Tēlepylos” (perhaps also a “Syriē”), and Crates was free to use the data from both adventurers in elaborating his own ideas of the zonal division of the globe. He perhaps elaborated it in a somewhat incoherent way, locating Homer’s Laestrygonians both with reference to the always visible circle of Rhodes taken as the arctic circle (misunderstanding or misrepresenting what Eudoxus/Aratus had said with reference to the constellation Draco), and with the latitude of the fixed arctic circle. The former was probably inspired by a cosmological doctrine that demanded the orderly 6–5–4 division of the cosmic sphere. Then again, it is also possible that it was he who was misunderstood or misrepresented by the scholiasts on Aratus; in this case Crates was consistent in associating the Laestrygonians with the latitude of the fixed arctic circle. A third possibility is that Eudoxus originally described the risings and settings of the sun, rather than Draco, but that it was he, rather than Crates, who associated these with the cosmological doctrine described above. Finally, taking into account the common mistakes in the determination of Draco’s declination (we know of a case when the mistake was as much as 12°), one cannot disregard the possibility of a mistake in Eudoxus’s—or, for that matter, Crates’—model, which would account for the difference. It was Crates’ model, however, that was depicted on the curious cosmological map discussed above. The question of the variability of the arctic circle was certainly one that Crates considered, although it—or one of the solutions of this problem—was most probably not represented on the map. By contrast, the cosmic (mytho-geographical) nature of Odysseus’s voyage,116 associated with the tropics, poles, and arctic circles, is indeed recognizable on the map, which makes it a unique graphic representation of Homeric exegesis. conclusion The two approaches to Homeric exegesis—Crates’ and Pytheas’s—analyzed in this paper are characterized by their use of mathematical geography in 116 Cf. Marinatos 2001; Käppel 2001: 16, 19, 21 Abb. 1; Nakassis 2004. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 323 the service of interpreting the poet’s narrative. Crates’ interpretative method was quite explicit, as he openly interpreted Homer’s narratives as legitimate scientific hypotheses. In this manner he developed a distinctive interpretation of Odysseus’s voyage, starting in our section of the inhabited earth but ending in the antoikoumenē, where Homeric Hades and other otherworldly locations were situated. The map discussed in the text could only have been made in connection with Crates’ unique approach to Homeric exegesis, being a graphic representation of his method and a counterpart to his famous globe. It is important to emphasize that both literary and graphic sources attest to an identical concept of the southern hemisphere. The literary sources are in disagreement, however, with respect to Crates’ ideas on the question of the fixed arctic circle as opposed to the always-visible, Draco-determined circle for the latitude of Greece. The Draco-determined arctic circle comes in turn to be associated with the question of the northern limit of the habitable zone. Thus, for example, Strabo explicitly associates the limit of the northern habitable zone with the projection onto the terrestrial globe of the always-visible circle as defined by the constellation of Ursa Major. By contrast, in Crates’ model the Homeric Laestrygonians were most probably placed on the fixed arctic circle, which defined the northern limit of the habitable zone for Eratosthenes, while Pytheas seems merely to have combined the data acquired on his voyage with certain Homeric references, particularly with those that he believed were concerned with meteorological phenomena in the far north. From the argument above, it seems reasonable to conjecture that Crates used the data he found in Pytheas’s account when elaborating his own ideas of mathematical geography. He thus combined the experiences of an imaginary (Odysseus) and a true adventurer (Pytheas). Pytheas’s account of the far north and, especially, solar phenomena in high northern latitudes is indeed very similar to certain parts of Homer’s narrative of the Laestrygonians. The reason for this could be simply the fact that Pytheas was inspired by the poet and that he (also) interpreted his narrative as referring to “scientific” hypotheses on solar phenomena in high northern latitudes. It could be argued that he received this notion through the medium of Eudoxus. Significantly, the constellation of Ursa Major formed the “Homeric” limits of sunrise and sunset already for Heraclitus, in what was a rather explicit allusion to the annual solar motion. In the end, it is impossible to determine who associated the solstitial latitude of the sun with the Draco/ Ursa Major-determined always-visible circle (Heraclitus, Hecataeus, Eudoxus, Aratus, or Crates), but it seems certain that of the notion arose from (at least) two interdependent factors: the latitude of Greece as the determinative for astronomical observations and the orderly 6–5–4 (“Pythagorean”) division 324 Tomislav Bilić of the cosmic sphere. In any case, the description of solstitial phenomena could be expressed in several ways: respective to the sphere of the fixed stars or with reference to the increasing length of summer days in high latitudes. The notions of the Laestrygonian “distant gates” and the solstitial island of Thoulē are dependent on both models. works cited Abel, K. 1974. “Zone.” Pauly-Wissowa Supp. 14: 989–1188. Ahmad, S. M. 1992. “Cartography of Al-Sharīf Al-Idrīsī.” In Harley and Woodward, eds. 156–74. Asmis, E. 1992. “Crates on Poetic Criticism.” Phoenix 46: 138–69. Aujac, G. 1987a. “The Growth of an Empirical Cartography in Hellenistic Greece.” In Harley and Woodward, eds. 148–60. —— 1987b. “Greek Cartography in the Early Roman World.” In Harley and Woodward, eds. 161–76. Ballabriga, A. 1986. Le Soleil et le Tartare: l’image mythique du monde en Grèce archaïque. Paris: Éditions de l’École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales. Banks, S. E. and Binns, J. W. 2002. Otia Imperialia: Recreation for an Emperor. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Berger, E. H. 1903. Geschichte der wissenschaftlichen Erdkunde der Griechen. 2nd ed. Leipzig: Veit & Comp. —— 1904. Mythische Kosmographie der Griechen. Leipzig: Teubner. Berggren, J. L. and Jones, A. 2000. Ptolemy’s Geography: An Annotated Translation of the Theoretical Chapters. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Bianchetti, S. 1998. Pitea di Massalia: L’Oceano. Pisa: Istituti Editoriali e Poligrafici Internazionali. Bilić, T. 2012. “Apollo, Helios and the Solstices in the Athenian, Delphian and Delian Calendars.” Numen 59: 509–32. Blomqvist, J. 2002. “The Geography of the Baltic in Greek Eyes—From Ptolemy to Laskaris Kananos.” In Amden, B. et al. eds. Noctes Atticae: 34 Articles on Graeco-Roman Antiquity and its Nachleben. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press. 36–51. Bowra, C. M. 1937. “The Proem of Parmenides.” CP 32: 97–112. Bridgman, T. P. 2005. Hyperboreans: Myth and History in Celtic-Hellenic Contacts. New York: Routledge. Broggiato, M. 2001. Cratete di Mallo: i frammenti. La Spezia: Agorà. Bunbury, E. H. 1883. A History of Ancient Geography among the Greeks and Romans. 2nd ed. 2 vols. London: John Murray. Burkert, W. 1972. Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Trans. by E. L. Minar Jr. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Burnet, J. 1920. Early Greek Philosophy. 3rd ed. London: A. and C. Black. Carpenter, R. 1973. Beyond the Pillars of Hercules: The Classical World Seen through the Eyes of its Discoverers. London: Tandem. Cary, M. and Warmington, E. H. 1963. The Ancient Explorers. Baltimore: Penguin. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 325 Cherniss, H. and Helmbold, W. C. 1957. Plutarch’s Moralia. Vol. 12. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Coxon, A. H. 2009. The Fragments of Parmenides. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing. Crawford, M. H. 1983. Roman Republican Coinage. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cunliffe, B. 2002. The Extraordinary Voyage of Pytheas the Greek. New York: Walker & Co. Dicks, D. R. 1960. Geographical Fragments of Hipparchus. London: Athlone Press. —— 1970. Early Greek Astronomy to Aristotle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Diggle, J. 1970. Euripides: Phaethon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Diller, A. 1934. “Geographical Latitudes in Eratosthenes, Hipparchus and Posidonius.” Klio 27: 258–69. —— 1975. “Pytheas of Massalia.” In Gillispie, C. ed. Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Vol. 11. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. 225–26. Dilke, O. A. W. 1985. Greek and Roman Maps. London: Thames and Hudson. Dolin, E. F. 1962. “Parmenides and Hesiod.” HSCP 66: 93–98. Dunlop, D. M. 1957. “The British Isles According To Medieval Arabic Authors.” The Islamic Quarterly 4: 11–28. Edson, E. and Savage-Smith, E. 2000. “An Astrologer’s Map: A Relic of Late Antiquity.” Imago Mundi 52: 7–29. Evans, J. and Berggren, J. L. 2006. Geminos’s Introduction to the Phenomena: A Translation and Study of a Hellenistic Survey of Astronomy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Ferrari, G. 2008. Alcman and the Cosmos of Sparta. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ferrari Pinney, G. and Sismondo Ridgway, B. 1981. “Herakles at the Ends of the Earth.” JHS 101: 141–44. Frame, D. 1978. The Myth of Return in Early Greek Epic. New Haven: Yale University Press. Freeman, K. 1996. Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Giampaglia, A. 1998. “Cratete di Mallo nel POxy 2888.” RIL 132: 503–18. Gisinger, F. 1963. “Pytheas 1.” Pauly-Wissowa 24: 314–66. Graf, F. 1993. Greek Mythology. Trans. by T. Marier. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Guthrie, W. K. C. 1965. A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol 2: The Presocratic Tradition from Parmenides to Democritus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Harley, J. B. and Woodward, D. eds. 1987. The History of Cartography. Vol. I: Cartography in Prehistoric, Ancient, and Medieval Europe and the Mediterranean. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. —— 1992. The History of Cartography. Vol. II, Pt. 1: Cartography in the Traditional Islamic and South Asian Societies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Havelock, E. A. 1958. “Parmenides and Odysseus.” HSCP 63: 133–43. —— 1978. The Greek Concept of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Heath, T. L. 1932 [1991]. Greek Astronomy. London: Dent and Sons (repr. Mineola, NY: Dover). Heidel, W. A. 1937. The Frame of the Ancient Greek Maps. New York: American Geographical Society. 326 Tomislav Bilić Heubeck, A. and Hoekstra, A. 1989. “Books IX–XII.” In Heubeck, A, Hoekstra, A., and West, S. eds. A Commentary on Homer’s Odyssey. Vol. II: Books IX–XVI. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hiatt, A. 2008. Terra Incognita: Mapping the Antipodes before 1600. London: The British Library. Holmes, T. R. 1907. Ancient Britain and the Invasion of Julius Caesar. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Jacob, C. 1988. “Écriture, géométrie et dessin figuratif: essai de lecture d’une carte grecque.” Mappemonde 1: 1–4. Janko, R. 2002. “The Derveni Papyrus: An Interim Text.” ZPE 141: 1–62. Jones, B. and Keillar, I. 1996. “Marinus, Ptolemy and the Turning of Scotland.” Britannia 27: 43–49. Kahn, C. H. 1964. “A New Look at Heraclitus.” American Philosophical Quarterly 1.3: 189–203 —— 1979. The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Käppel, L. 2001. “Bilder des Nordens im frühen antiken Griechenland.” In EngelBraunschmidt, A. et al. eds. Ultima Thule: Bilder des Nordens von der Antike bis zur Gegenwart. Frankfurt: Lang. 11–27. Kennedy, E. S. and Kennedy, M.-H. 1987. “Al-Kāshī’s Geographical Table.” TAPS 77: 1–45. Keyser, P. T. 2001. “The Geographical Work of Dikaiarchos.” In Fortenbaugh, W. W. and Schütrumpf, E. eds. Dicaearchus of Messana: Text, Translation, and Discussion. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. 353–72. Kidd, D. 1997. Aratus: Phaenomena. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kidd, I. G. 1988. Posidonius. Volume II: The Commentary. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kiessling, W. 1914. “ Ῥίπαια ὄρη.” Pauly-Wissowa 12.1: 846–916. Kirk, G. S. 1962. Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——, Raven, J. E., and Schofield, M. 1983. The Presocratic Philosophers. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kouremenos, T., Parássoglou, G. M., and Tsantsanoglou, K. 2006. The Derveni Papyrus. Florence: Olschki. Kroll, W. 1922. “Krates 16.” Pauly-Wissowa 11.22: 1634–41. Lebedev, A. V. 1989. “Heraclitus in P. Derveni.” ZPE 79: 39–47. Lehmann-Haupt, C. F. 1921. “Kimmerier.” Pauly-Wissowa 11.21: 397–434. Lucas, D. W. 1968. Aristotle: Poetics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Lundström, V. 1902. Laskaris Kananos’ Reseanteckningar från de nordiska länderna. Upsala/ Leipzig: Lundequist/Harrassowitz. Macurdy, G. H. 1920. “The Hyperboreans Again, Abaris, and Helixoia.” CR 34: 137–41. Mair, A. W. and Mair, G. R. 1921. Callimachus: Hymns and Epigrams. Lycophron. Aratus. London: Heinemann. Marcovich, M. 2001. Heraclitus. 2nd ed. Sankt Augustin: Academia. Marinatos, N. 2001. “The Cosmic Journey of Odysseus.” Numen 48: 381–416. McCready, W. D. 1996. “Isidore, the Antipodeans, and the Shape of the Earth.” Isis 87: 108–27. Crates of Mallos and Pytheas of Massalia 327 McKirahan, R. D. 2010. Philosophy before Socrates. 2nd ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Merry, W. W., Riddell, J., and Monro, D. B. 1886–1901. Homer’s Odyssey. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Mette, H. J. 1936. Sphairopoiia: Untersuchungen zur Kosmologie des Krates von Pergamon. Munich: Beck. —— 1952. Pytheas von Massalia. Berlin: de Gruyter. Minorsky, V. 1970. Hudūd al-‘Ālam: The Regions of the World. A Persian Geography. 2nd ed. Ed. by C. E. Bosworth. London: Luzac. Mommsen, T. H. 1895. C. Iulii Solini Collectanea rerum memorabilium. Berlin: Weidmann. Morgan, K. 2000. Myth and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Morrison, J. S. 1955. “Parmenides and Er.” JHS 75: 59–68. Mourelatos, A. 2008. The Route of Parmenides. 2nd ed. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing. Müllenhoff, K. 1870. Deutsche Altertumskunde. Vol. 1. Berlin: Weidmann. Murphy, J. P. 1977. Rufus Festus Avienus: Ora Maritima. Chicago: Ares. Nakassis, D. 2004. “Gemination at the Horizons: East and West in the Mythical Geography of Archaic Greek Epic.” TAPA 134: 215–33. Nansen, F. 1911. In Northern Mists: Arctic Exploration in Early Times. 2 vols. London: Heinemann. Neubauer, A. 1864. “Assaph hebraeus.” In Benfey, T. ed. Orient und Occident insbesondere in ihren gegenseitigen Beziehungen. Vol. 2. Göttingen: Dieterich. 657–76. Neugebauer, O. 1972. “On Some Aspects of Early Greek Astronomy.” PAPS 116: 243–51. —— 1975a. “A Greek World Map.” In Bingen, J., Cambier, G., and Nachtergael, G. eds. Le Monde grec: pensée, littérature, histoire, documents. Hommages à Claire Préaux. Brussels: Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles. 312–17. —— 1975b. A History of Ancient Mathematical Astronomy. Vol. 2. Berlin: Springer. Nicolai, R. 1984. “Un sistema di localizzazione relativa: Aorsi e Siraci in Strab. XI 5, 7.8.” In Prontera, F. ed. Strabone: contributi allo studio della personalità e dell’opera. Vol. I. Perugia: Università degli Studi. 101–25. Packard, L. R. 1874. “On a Passage in Homer’s Odyssey (x. 81–86).” TAPA 5: 31–41. Page, D. 1973. Folktales in Homer’s Odyssey. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Parroni, P. 1984. “Surviving Sources of the Classical Geographers through Late Antiquity and the Medieval Period.” Arctic 37: 352–58. Pocock, L. G. 1958. “Gadflies and the Laestrygonians.” CR 8: 109–11. —— 1968. “A Note on Odyssey 10. 86.” CQ 18: 1–3. Porter, J. I. 1992. “Hermeneutic Lines and Circles: Aristarchus and Crates on the Exegesis of Homer.” In Lamberton, R. and Keaney, J. J. eds. Homer’s Ancient Readers: The Hermeneutics of Greek Epic’s Earliest Exegetes. Princeton: Princeton University Press. 67–114. —— 2003. Review of Broggiato 2001. BMCRev 2003.11.33. Purves, A. C. 2010. Space and Time in Ancient Greek Narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Quinn, K. 1982. “The Poet and his Audience in the Augustan Age.” ANRW 30.1: 75–180. Roller, D. W. 2006. Through the Pillars of Herakles: Greco-Roman Exploration of the Atlantic. London: Routledge. 328 Tomislav Bilić Romm, J. S. 1992. The Edges of the Earth in Ancient Thought: Geography, Exploration, and Fiction. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Roseman, C. H. 1994. Pytheas of Massalia: On the Ocean. Chicago: Ares. Rosenthal, F. 1967. Ibn Khaldun: The Muqaddimah. An Introduction to History. 3 vols. 2nd ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Schönbeck, L. 1993. “Heraclitus Revisited (Pap. Derveni Col. I Lines 7–11).” ZPE 95: 7–22. Seaford, R. 2004. Money and the Early Greek Mind: Homer, Philosophy, Tragedy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stahl, W. H. and Burge, E. L. 1977. Martianus Capella and the Seven Liberal Arts. Vol. II: The Marriage of Philology and Mercury. New York: Columbia University Press. Steele, L. D. 2002. “Mesopotamian Elements in the Proem of Parmenides? Correspondences between the Sun-Gods Helios and Shamash.” CQ 52: 583–88. Stevens, W. M. 1980. “The Figure of the Earth in Isidore’s De natura rerum.” Isis 71: 268–77. Stokes, M. C. 1963. “Hesiodic and Milesian Cosmogonies II.” Phronesis 8: 1–34. Taylor, E. G. R. 1956. “A Letter Dated 1577 from Mercator to John Dee.” Imago Mundi 13: 56–68. Thomson, J. O. 1948. History of Ancient Geography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tibbetts, G. R. 1992. “The Beginnings of a Cartographic Tradition.” In Harley and Woodward, eds. 90–107. Tierney, J. J. 1967. Dicuili liber de mensura orbis terrae. Dublin: Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies. Tozer, H. F. 1897. A History of Ancient Geography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Trent Foley, W. and Holder, A. G. 1999. Bede: A Biblical Miscellany. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press. Uhden, R. 1936. “Die Weltkarte des Martianus Capella.” Mnemosyne 3: 97–124. van Thiel, H. 2000. Scholia D in Iliadem. Köln: Proecdosis. Vos, H. 1963. “Die Bahnen von Nacht und Tag.” Mnemosyne 16: 18–34. Waitz, G. 1876. Adami Gesta Hammaburgensis ecclesiae pontificum ex recensione Lappenbergii. 2nd ed. Hannover: Hahn. Walbank, F. W. 1948. “The Geography of Polybius.” C&M 9: 155–82. Repr. in id. 2002. Polybius, Rome, and the Hellenistic World: Essays and Reflections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 31–52. West, M. L. 1966. Hesiod: Theogony. Oxford: Clarendon Press. —— 1997. The East Face of Helicon: West Asiatic Elements in Early Greek Poetry and Myth. Oxford: Oxford University Press. —— 2005. “Odyssey and Argonautica.” CQ 55: 39–64. Whitaker, I. 1981/82. “The Problem of Pytheas’ Thule.” CJ 77: 148–64. Woodbury, L. 1966. “Equinox at Acragas: Pindar, Ol. 2.61–62.” TAPA 97: 597–616. Wooding, J. M. 2000. “Monastic Voyaging and the Navigatio.” In Wooding, J. M. ed. The Otherworld Voyage in Early Irish Literature. Dublin: Four Courts Press. 226–45. Wrede, W. 1937. “Odysseus.” Pauly-Wissowa 17:1905–96.