Imprint Academic Ltd. "PARRHESIA" AND THE "DEMOS TYRANNOS": FRANK SPEECH, FLATTERY AND ACCOUNTABILITY IN DEMOCRATIC ATHENS Author(s): Matthew Landauer Source: History of Political Thought, Vol. 33, No. 2 (Summer 2012), pp. 185-208 Published by: Imprint Academic Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/26225766 Accessed: 03-01-2018 14:39 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Imprint Academic Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to History of Political Thought This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS: FRANK SPEECH, FLATTERY AND ACCOUNTABILITY IN DEMOCRATIC ATHENS Matthew Landauer Abstract: Parrhesia, or frank speech, is usually understood as a practice intimately connected to Athenian democracy. This paper begins by analysing parrhesia in non-democratic regimes. Building on that analysis, I suggest that most accounts of parrhesia overlook the degree to which its practice at Athens implied a comparison of the demos to an unaccountable ruler — a tyrant. As a practice, parrhesia was paradigmatically undertaken by speakers addressing an audience with the power to sanction them in the event that their advice proved uncongenial. As such it could be useful in both democracies and autocracies, serving as a possible counterweight to flattering rhetoric. But in both regime types it was in essence a remedial virtue, neces sitated by a basic structural feature common to both autocratic and Athenian demo cratic decision procedures: at the centre of both was an unaccountable decision maker able to hold its advisors to account. Introduction The Greek wordparrhesia, literally meaning 'saying everything',3 was deployed in fifth- and fourth-century Greek literature in two broad senses. On the one hand, it could connote thoughtless, careless, impudent speech. Thus Isocrates in the Aeropagiticus, in comparing the contemporary fourth-century democ racy unfavourably with the regime founded by Solon and Cleisthenes, lists parrhesia, along with license (akolasia), lawlessness (paranomia) and a gen eral sense of entitlement among the citizens to do whatever they please (iexousian ton panta poieiri) as lamentable features of contemporary Athenian life.4 On the other hand, parrhesia could connote free speech, both as a privi lege granted by a political regime and as the practice of frank speakers, even (or especially) in the face of personal risk. Parrhesia in these positive senses has recently been analysed within a variety of fifth- and fourth-century Athenian contexts, and the literature explores the many ways in which the practice was intimately connected to 1 Committee on Social Studies, Harvard University, Hilles Library, 59 Shepard St, Cambridge, MA 02138, USA. Email: landauer@fas.harvard.edu 2 The author would like to thank Mary Dietz, Jennifer London, Harvey Mansfield, Eric Nelson, Emma Saunders-Hastings, Joel Schlosser, Christina Tarnopolsky, Richard Tuck, and audiences at the MPSA Annual Conference in 2009 and the Harvard Political Theorv WorkshoD for heloful comments on Drevious versions of this naner 3 The Greek roots are 'pan' (all) and 'rhesis' or 'rhema' (speech). 4 Isocrates, Aeropagiticus, in the Loeb Isocrates, Vol. 2, trans. G. Norlin (Cam bridge, MA, 1929), para. 20.7. Citations of Isocrates in this paper come from the three-volume Loeb edition, with some translations modified. HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT. Vol. XXXIII. No. 2. Summer 2012 This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 186 M. LANDAUER Athenian democracy.5 Parrhesia i in the Assembly, serving as a pos potentially deceptive rhetoric and crucial to a successful debate.6 Mo resonated deeply with Athenian p describes the [parrhesia]', democratic and modern city as scholars democratic Athens.7 Arlene Sax shamelessness, sees it as funda regime that 'breaks from the reve on the present and the future'.8 Athens' Sara self-conception', Monoson, is funda emphasizing picture of a democratic city cal, insight with an inverse parr teem imag again, Plato's Republic offers a w tion of the tyrannical regime, one former allies, on the grounds tha each other and to him, criticizing of parrhesia linked ens: to the 'the treated as under general practice a sign, tyranny and anti-tyrannic of parrhesia indeed as i proof, 5 Scholarly work has linked parrhe parrhesia' s relationship to comedy, Speech in Classical Athens', Journa J. Henderson, 'Attic Old Comedy F Empire, and the Arts in Fifth-Centur bridge, MA, 1998), pp. 255-74. For pa see S. Monoson, Plato's Democratic R. Balot, 'Free Speech, Courage, and sical Antiquity, ed. I. SluiterandR.M. ship to emotions such as shame see (Princeton, 2010), ch. 3; and A. Saxo Athens (Cambridge, 2006), esp. ch. 2. ideology more broadly, see Monoson along with Elizabeth Markovits, The P 6 Monoson, Entanglements, pp. 60-2; contrast between parrhesia and rheto 7 Plato, Republic, in Complete Wor 8 Saxonhouse, Free Speech, 9 Ibid., p. 214. 10 Plato, Republic, 567c. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms p. 209. PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 187 home ... and were now in fact living as free citizens'.11 By and large, ature on parrhesia and democratic Athens offers an attractive pictu Athenian demos adhering to a popular ideology with a strong, partic critical ethic of parrhesia at its core. Even scholars critical of some a this picture, or sceptical of how well parrhesia actually functioned, a its important place in democratic ideology.12 The flourishing research on parrhesia's relationship to democracy been matched, however, with sustained consideration of its plac democratic regimes.13 This is unfortunate for two reasons. First, o t"~" " —— ...νν..τ.ν.ν ..xxwxx " w xV~v.^ vui; context. But more importantly, a consideratio to function in autocracies can and should be clarify our understanding of how it funct Parrhesia, I argue, was paradigmatically prac audience with the power to reward or sanctio as this is true, parrhesia was not so much a no as co-equals jointly and freely deciding on a weighing the possible options, as it was a nor individual offering advice to a decision make such it could be practised, in both democrac virtue, necessitated by a structural feature c Athenian democratic decision procedures: at countable decision maker able to hold advisers tus of this form of parrhesia is underscored w 11 Monoson, Entanglements, p. 55. For a discussio and self-representation' as pertaining to tyranny Glue: the Function of Tyranny in Fifth-Century Tyranny, ed. K. Morgan (Austin, 2003), pp. 59-94 12 See, for example, Markovits, Politics of Sincer from Monoson's account of how Plato and Socrates parrhesia. She is also sceptical of the value of 'stra arguing that parrhesia, at its worst, was merely anot theless, she largely accepts Monoson's account democratic ideology. See also Saxonhouse, Free Sp exploration of problems with the practice of parrh seven), without, however, denying its close associa 13 But see J. London, 'How to do things with Fab in Stories from KalTla Wa Dimna', History of Politi ment of a kind of parrhesia in an autocratic (but no cusses parrhesia's function in Hellenistic courts in h (Cambridge, 1997). See below, n. 24, for more on K in autocracies. 14 I am here drawing a distinction between 'delib the Greeks may not have drawn such a sharp divisi tinction in mind helps to clarify how parrhesia fun This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 188 M. LANDAUER usage of the term: parrhesia could with relative impunity — one tha ers.15 Supporters of the Athenian nature of democracies to grant thi Athenian democracy required it parrhesia strongly suggests that t not consistently protected. If it w risky in the first place? One mig offering bold counsel in the face cratic virtue only insofar as the tyrant. The argument of the article proceeds as follows. In the first section, I explore texts in which parrhesia is explicitly discussed in autocratic contexts. Here I show that Athenians such as Isocrates thought that parrhesia was important in autocratic as well as democratic settings: parrhesia could serve as a possible counterweight to flattery, itself engendered by the autocrat's position as sole, unaccountable decision maker, with the power to reward and punish his advisers. Having shown that the need for parrhesia in autocracies arose from the power asymmetry between adviser and decision maker, I argue in the following sections that a similar asymmetry of power obtained in demo cratic Athens. In Section II, I turn to an analysis of ancient explorations of accountability and its absence in both tyrannies and democratic Athens, and emphasize the structural basis for the rise of the image of the unaccountable demos, analogized to the tyrant: Voters in the Assembly, and Jurors in the popular courts, were thoroughly insulated from Athens' otherwise extensive network of accountability mechanisms, while simultaneously collectively wielding the power to hold individual citizens accountable. The power asym metries in the Assembly, I argue, thus parallelled those between the autocrat and his advisers. This analogy provides the background for the argument of 15 Here I depart somewhat from D.M. Carter's claim that parrhesia was merely an 'attribute', 'something that the citizen of one city was more likely to display than that of another', and a characteristic that Athenians displayed merely as 'a sort of side effect of their political enfranchisement'. See D.M. Carter, 'Citizen Attribute, Negative Right: A Conceptual Difference Between Ancient and Modern Ideas of Freedom of Speech', in Free Speech in Classical Antiquity, ed. Sluiter and Rosen, pp. 198-9.1 agree with Carter that it would be wrong to conceive of parrhesia as a 'right', given that it was not abso lutely protected by law. Yet parrhesia was also more than just a citizen attribute, since it was conceived of not merely as a 'side effect' of political enfranchisement, but as some thing that could be granted and encouraged (or forbidden and discouraged) by the regime. Moreover, as 1 explore below, many Athenians expected that granting and encouraging parrhesia would have positive effects. As I argue throughout this article, the word parrhesia could refer both to a privilege of free speech that could be promoted or restricted by the regime, and also to a practice or attribute that could be exercised by citizens, whether or not the privilege of parrhesia was well protected (although, to be sure, where it was not well protected one might expect to find less of it). This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 189 Section III, where I argue that the discourse surrounding parrh tery in Athens was predicated on important similarities betwee cratic Assembly and an autocrat. I conclude with the implica analysis for how we should understand Athenian Assembly generally. Parrhesia in Autocracies In spite of parrhesia's democratic pedigree and associations, there are a num ber of discussions in fourth-century Athenian literature of parrhesia in auto cratic settings. Thus, for example, Aristotle's Constitution of the Athenians contains a single reference to parrhesia, which, strikingly, is divorced from the democratic context. As Aristotle tells it, a farmer was busy working one day on a plot of marginal land when the tyrant Peisistratus happened by: Peisistratus saw someone working an area that was all stones, and, being surprised, told his attendant to ask what the land produced. 'Aches and pains,' the farmer replied; 'Peisistratus ought to take his 10 per cent of the aches and pains too.' The man made the reply not knowing that he was speaking to Peisistratus, while the latter was delighted at his frankness [parrhesia] and industriousness, and exempted him from all taxation.16 Scholars who have commented on this passage tend to downplay its impor tance or quickly move to interpret it within the context of democratic Athens. Sara Monoson sees it as playing on the incongruity of parrhesia being found in a tyranny at all, while Arlene Saxonhouse believes it to reveal more about the values of Aristotle's fourth-century Athenian contemporaries than the prevalence of 'frank speaking' under Peisistratus' fifth-century tyranny.17 On one level, Saxonhouse is surely right. If we take the story as a tale that fourth-century Athenians told themselves, it says as much or more about their own self-image as it does about how parrhesia might have functioned in tyr annies: the Athenians are proud of their reputation for boldness and frank ness. We cannot extrapolate much from this anecdote. Aristotle presents the story in the context of a discussion of the moderateness of Peisistratus' tyr anny; and given the farmer's ignorance of his conversational partner's real identity, it is questionable whether the farmer's quip should count as an exam ple of parrhesia at all. Yet the story also opens the question of parrhesia's function in non-democratic regimes and of the attitudes of autocrats towards its practice. The tyrant in Plato's Republic thought parrhesia a danger to his regime, a practice he could not tolerate. Why in contrast did Peisistratus find the farmer's frankness delightful? 16 Aristotle, Constitution of Athens, in The Politics and the Constitution of Athens, ed. S. Everson (Cambridge, 1996), 16.6. 17 Monoson, Entanglements, p. 55; Saxonhouse, Free Speech, p. 90. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 190 M. LANDAUER Two letters, written by Isocrates t Peisistratus had good reason to be one to Antipater, who served as Ph Nicocles, a king on the island of Cy The letter to Antipater contains th For it stands to reason that it is bec speak to please [tous aei pros hedo only monarchies cannot endure — inevitable dangers — but even con well, though they enjoy greater secu speak with absolute frankness in fav parresiazomenous] seem Those doomed who to that many destruction.18 are accustomed thin to thi cratic practice, should find Isocrate both autocratic and democratic regi be claiming that it is even more imp on the contrast between those who parrhesia in favour of what is best gers', while the advice of the latter Yet on Isocrates' speakers, they are account, often while seduced into Antipater, Isocrates illustrates this dent, Diodotus, and his experience 'because of his frankness [dia to pa best interests', was deprived of th service while 'the flattery of men his own good services'.19 Similarly, ter to Nicocles that since most asso their favour [pros charin homilous of parrhesia and criticism crucial t Nicocles and Antipater should be p to speak with parrhesia, then, prim advisers is to flatter the autocrat. Th position as sole unaccountable decis punish his advisers. Given this posit to tell him what they think he want him what they think is the best a endeavour, that 18 19 Ibid. risk: and one's Isocrates, To Diodotus' audience experien may Antipater, 20 Isocrates, To Nicocles, Loeb, Vol. 1, trans. G. Norlin, paras. 3-4. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms not Loeb, a Vol. PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 191 asymmetry between speaker and audience gives rise to a particularly cious form of advice-giving — flattering speeches, aiming not at 'the b 'to gratify'. This form of speech nullifies the immediate danger speaker, since the end result — if the speech is successful — is a gra audience. Nonetheless, it is ultimately, in Isocrates' view, destructive f ruler: 'monarchies cannot endure' when advice aims at gratification a good policy. We can imagine that, at the limit, the flattery endemic t asymmetric power relations leads to a vicious circle: advisers, fearin their positions, tell the autocrat what he wants to hear; the autocrat r those who gratify and flatter him, reinforcing the incentive to flatter. cess feeds on itself, with advice tending further and further away fro policy, until the autocrat's rule collapses. Isocrates' letters offer two potential ways out of the vicious circle. Fi autocrat can try to mitigate the problem by creating a climate favour parrhesia, i.e. by allowing and even encouraging his advisers to offer their best advice frankly rather than to flatter him. This is the main t Isocrates' advice to Antinater and Nicocles. As Isocrates tells Antioater. 'those who declare the truth should be esteemed more than those who, saying everything in order to gratify, speak nothing worthy of gratitude'.21 Nicocles, too, is advised to encourage frank speech. He is counselled to regard as trust worthy not those who praise everything he says and does, but those who point out his mistakes. He should 'grant parrhesia' (didou parrhesian) to 'those with good judgment' (tois eu phronousin) — that is, allow and encourage those with good judgment to speak freely and frankly — and distinguish between 'artful flatterers' (tous technei kolakeuontas) and those who 'serve him with goodwill' (tous met' eunoias therapeuontas).22 Isocrates thus coun sels both Nicocles and Antipater to make frankness less risky by granting the privilege of free speech (didonai parrhesian) to at least some advisers and esteeming and rewarding those who speak frankly rather than those who flatter. Yet in recounting the story of Diodotus, who took it upon himself to prac tice parrhesia even in an inhospitable context, Isocrates offers another, dis tinct possibility: an adviser can speak up for the best even in situations where 21 Isocrates, To Antipater, para. 7. 22 Isocrates, To Nicocles, paras. 27-8. Cf. Carter, 'Citizen Attribute, Negative Right', p. 211: Ί am not aware of any accounts of historical tyrants restricting free speech... a tyrant sees little need actively to discourage free speech when his very person is discouraging enough... Becauseparrhesia is only an attribute, and not anyone's right, it is not so much something a tyrant actively restricts, as something his subjects are indis posed to exercise.' That Isocrates attempts to get Nicocles and Antipater to 'grant parrhesia' to their advisers suggests that even if we accept Carter's distinction between a tyrant's 'actively' restricting free speech versus discouraging it (passively?) through his 'very person', parrhesia was still seen as something an autocrat or tyrant could promote, e.g. by attempting to establish it as a privilege. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 192 M. LANDAUER it is likely that the autocrat does adviser's actions parallel the pract sider, for example, Demosthenes' First Philippic·. I have spoken my plain sentiments it is to your interest to receive th were equally certain that to offer speaker ... But, as it is, in the unce may be for myself, yet in the con adopt it, I have ventured to addres In speaking up bravely in favour o the autocrat's adviser, like Demos tary critique. Moreover, in both willingness to take on the risk of itself possible evidence of his trus and as Demosthenes suggests to h Yet the presence of risk in the a in its effects. It is perhaps true th inherent in speaking frankly to t This might suggest that the risks advice is given. On the other han chief forms of pernicious advice contingent on pleasing the autocr Indeed, Isocrates' advice to the au wise, and his attempts to get Ant frankness more generally, suggest speech is, the less likely one is to lege of parrhesia is not granted fr practised; the risk of but there speaking is no guarant frankly.24 It is worth stressing that Isocrat an idealized portrait of the relati 23 Demosthenes 4.51, quoted in Mon D. Konstan, Friendship in the analysis of Isocrates' letter to Antipat 24 Cf. counselor, who must risk the ire of p dicted, even if the advice is in their o that obtains between frank speaker an speak the truth in such a context repr prized.' Konstan's focus on friendship ties between the practice of parrhesia make the focus of this article. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 193 here.25 It is true that he is keen to portray his own relationship with Nicocles as one marked by frankness, not flattery. This can be contrasted with Isocrates' advice to his pupils, in the Antidosis and elsewhere, that it might sometimes be necessary to 'pay court' to the demos at Athens, to practise therapeia, flattery. Indeed, in the Antidosis, Isocrates notes that one of his pupils, the general Timotheus, failed in his trial before the demos precisely because he refused to flatter them.26 Yet it would be a mistake to take Timotheus's relationship to the demos as exemplary of the orator-demos relationship while taking Isocrates' description of his own relationship with Nicocles as exemplary of the adviser-autocrat relationship more generally. This would be to overlook the degree to which Isocrates, throughout his advice to Nicocles and Antipater, remains aware that the problem of flattery is ever present in, and even built into the adviser-autocrat relationshio. For everv Timotheus. who ultimatelv failed at democratic politics because of his refusal to pay court to the demos, Isocrates offers a Diodotus, whose parrhesia and refusal to flatter autocrats caused him equal amounts of trouble. Isocrates has thus offered two possible solutions to the problem of flattery in autocracies, engendered by the autocrat's position as unaccountable deci sion maker. But it is not yet clear how this discussion of parrhesia in autocra cies might bear on the democratic experience. After all, much seems to differentiate the practice of parrhesia in democracies and autocracies. Not the least important is the institutional context in which parrhesia is deployed: in a democracy, the Assembly is the decision-making body, while in an autocracy, a single man decides. There is also the question of who gets to speak with parrhesia: it is likely that the circle of advisers to an autocrat would be smaller than the set of possible advisers to a democratic Assembly, even accepting the fact that the right to speak at the Assembly, while guaranteed to all citizens, would have been exercised by relatively few. Moreover, Isocrates' recom mendation to Nicocles to grant parrhesia to those with good judgment, and not to all his subjects, reinforces the idea that parrhesia in an autocracy may well have been more limited in scope than in a democracy.27 Given these dif ferences, it might be argued that Isocrates, in keeping with his constitutional pluralism, was simply engaged in transferring some Athenian political know how to a foreign regime or two — if parrhesia had been so successful at 25 Cf. Κ. Morgan, 'The Tyranny of the Audience in Plato and Isocrates', in Popular Tyranny, pp. 181-213. In her view, according to Isocrates, 'the king-advisor relationship is marked by freedom, whereas the orator-demos relationship is marked by flattery (p. 186). 26 On Timotheus, see Isocrates, Antidosis, 130-3. See also Morgan, 'Tyranny of the Audience', pp. 186-7.1 accept Morgan's claim that Isocrates tells his pupils to flatter the demos, at least sometimes, but do not agree with her that he does not recognize the same need in autocratic contexts. 27 Although, as I argue below, this is not a clear-cut issue — the Attic orators often claim that they, and speakers like them, are not granted parrhesia either. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 194 M. LANDAUER ensuring good decision making at to the less egalitarian climate of a regimes.28 If so, perhaps parrhes about its practice in a democracy. quickly dismiss the significance o cratic case for understanding its p next section to a broader analysis absence) in Greek discussions of b prepare in the ground for a discussio Athens. Accountability As we saw in the and its previous A sect granted from above or offered fro problem of flattery, a problem in tional position and the power asym section, I explore the tropes in fi underpinning this description of t unaccountability of the autocrat, the wake of these images of the u claims about the Athenian demos, has called the 'critical community analogy between fourth-century ground, analogy: argue and the that so here claim this demos critiques I that and of tyr Athe emphasiz the rhetorical demo move analogizing the unaccountability o a very real fact about the lighted ability. 28 On While most Isocratean forms of constitutional po plur pp. 182, 188-91. 29 See J. Ober, Political Dissent in D 30 The literature on the tyrant-d S. Forsdyke, 'The Uses and Abuses of Political Thought, ed. R. Balot (Oxford to the Popular Tyranny volume. The t Athens was sometimes said to rule o Thucydides' Peloponnesian War, for ex getting 'that your empire is a despoti spirators', in The Landmark Thucydid The actions of the demos at home wer dealings 'Uses with elites. For examples and Abuses', pp. 239^10. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms an PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 195 subjected citizens who took part to multiple accountability procedure and Assemblymen were privileged within this system, holding o account but accountable to no one. The 'constitutional debate' in Herodotus' Histories is an important early source for the trope of autocratic unaccountability. Here, Otanes criticizes monarchy as the form of government where 'it is possible for the ruler to do what he pleases without having to render an account [aneuthunoi]'.31 Such freedom from restraints would render any man a bad ruler: 'give this power to the best man on earth, and it would stir him to unwonted thoughts'.32 On the other hand, Otanes identifies the accountability of magistrates as one of the three hallmarks of 'rule by the majority', along with selection of magistrates by lot and the referral of all proposals to the public.33 The autocrat's rule, at least according to Otanes, is thus characterized by his ability to do whatever he desires, with impunity, and without having to justify those actions. The autocrat's reputation for unaccountable rule in accordance with his own desires would become a commonplace, and would crystallize around the figure of a particular kind of autocrat — the tyrant. Plato's depictions in the Gorgias and Republic of the tyrant's limitless desires and boundless transgres sions of custom and law implicitly trade on the tyrant's unaccountability.34 In the Politics, Aristotle identifies tyranny in the 'fullest degree', 'the counter part or universal monarcny , as tne sort or tyranny tnat "exercises unaccount able [anupeuthunos] rule over subjects . . . with a view to its own private interest and not in the interest of the persons ruled'.35 While both Plato and Aristotle left some room for the possibility of a good single ruler, democratic ideology tended to collapse the distinction between tyranny and monarchy. Yet the critique of the tyrant as an irresponsible, unaccountable ruler repre sented a crucial point of agreement between the critics of the Athenian democracy and exponents of its ideology.36 Thus Aeschines, in his speech Against Ctesiphon, told the jurors, 'There are, as you know, fellow-citizens, three forms of government in the world tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy. Tyrannies and oligarchies are administered according to the tempers of their lords, but democratic states according to their own established laws.'37 The administration of Athens, in contrast with tyrannies, consisted in part in there being 'nothing in all the state that is exempt from audit [anupeuthunon], 31 Herodotus, Histories, Loeb, Vol. 2 (Cambridge, MA, 1950), 3.80. 32 Ibid. 33 Ibid. 34 Plato, Gorgias, trans. J.H. Nichols, Jr. (Ithaca, 1998), 466c^470a. 35 Aristotle, Politics, 1295a. 36 See J. Ober, 'Tyrant Killing as Therapeutic Stasis: A Political Debate in Images and Texts', in Popular Tyranny, ed. Morgan, p. 215. 37 Aeschines, Against Ctesiphon, para. 6. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 196 M. LANDAUER investigation, and examination'.3 tyrant stood as the antithesis of de Athens were held accountable, the t Yet not all observers and participa Aeschines' claim that nothing and investigation, and examination'. At l ics of the democracy pointing to e Wasps, Philocleon glories in his and gleefully recounting the benefits for doing all this we can't be called other office holders can claim.' Her unaccountability using the language of tyrants, begins to blur the line b Xenophon's account of the illegal battle of Arginusae (406 BC), for th triremes had been destroyed, also analogy. In the aftermath of the b fault for the disaster began almost bly that the generals be called to ac not pick up the shipwrecked men'. Xenophon contrasts the accountabi status: when one Euryptolemus tri try the generals collectively, for h writes that the majority of the Ass would be terrible if someone were wished'.41 As Sara Forsdyke has no wished' recalls 'the traditional port wants without being held to accoun The strangeness of the anecdote — Assembly, some three-thousand in unison? — highlights the comparis demos and tyrant. In Xenophon's v the asymmetry of accountability a later, the Athenians repented [the who had deceived the demos be pr 38 Ibid., para. 22. Indeed, Aeschines tak rule that he makes the claim twice; cf. 3. free 39 from the audit Aristophanes, who has Wasps, in held the any pu Loeb A bridge, MA, 1998), lines 578-87. 40 Xenophon, Hellenica, 1.7.4. 41 Ibid., 42 Forsdyke, 1.7.12, translation 'Uses and mine. Abuses', This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms p. 2 PARRHES1A AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 197 until they were tried; and among them was Callixeinus. Callixein found guilty, and although he escaped before his trial during the tum period of oligarchic revolution, he is reputed to have starved to deat his return to Athens, apparently universally detested for the role he p the affair. It is uncontroversial that the demos was responsible for the to try the generals collectively; indeed, the Assemblymen's resp Euryptolemus that they should not be prevented from doing what the suggests that the members of the Assembly viewed themselves as the sible agents, at least at this point in time. Nonetheless, when the decision the generals collectively comes to be recognized as a poor oiie, the d not held accountable. Rather, the demos holds others to account: acc ity is borne solely by the proposers of the decree, who are charg deceiving the people.44 Aeschines' claims for the comprehensiveness of Athenian instituti accountability notwithstanding, the analogy to tyranny — at least with to this issue — was not inapt. The crucial point was not whether accoun was central to Athenian democratic theory and practice (it was), answer to the following question: who at Athens was accountable to In both the fifth- and fourth-century Athenian democracy, institutions to hold citizens participating in politics accountable to the polis; and f mid-fifth century on, accountability to the polis increasingly meant ability to the people, in the Assembly and in the Courts, even while participating in these forums were themselves unaccountable.45 In keeping with Otanes' description of 'rule by the majority', mag were subject to a number of procedures before, after, and, in excep cases, during, their term of office. At the dokimasia ton archon, a po magistrate selected by election or sortition could subsequently be reje not meeting citizenship or age requirements, or if he had been found a crime punishable with atimia (loss of citizenship rights). Held befo ular jury, the dokimasia procedure also allowed any citizen to come and require the prospective magistrate to explain and defend his past 43 Xenophon, Hellenica, 1.7.35, translation mine. 44 See also my discussion of Diodotus' speech in Thucydides' Peloponnesia below, fn. 72, and of Aristotle's account of final democracy and its relatio below, p. 206. 45 The rise of popular institutions of accountability was an important aspec development of popular sovereignty at Athens throughout the fifth century. Man accountability institutions discussed in this paragraph had pre-democratic, non precursors. For example, it is likely that archons originally faced their dokima the Aereopagus, rather than popular courts. For an attempt at reconstructing the cal development of the institutions of accountability in the fifth century, see M. From Popular Sovereignty to the Sovereignty of Law (Berkeley, 1986), pp. 40- This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 198 M. LANDAUER and way of life.46 Upon completio through the euthunai. At the euth all public funds used and disbursed actions more generally. Both citiz sations against an outgoing magis positive malfeasance, and charges Finally, during their tenure mag ment procedures such as the eisan of public trust, such as treason, s result in a trial before the Assemb successful eisangelia trial was dea Orators in the Assembly, holding the dokimasia ton archon or euth served to hold them accountable about immediate audience respons ous response of the demos which c mally, orators were potentially s mid-fifth century on, were also l name of unlawful the latter charge sugge or unconstitutional prop had been found to be un proposal Tried before a popular the annulment of the court, a suc decree and from the merely nominal to the c tially accountable for the advice t their actions and could be punished tion of a popular jury. Individual Athenians actively par selves called upon to give an accou by their fellow citizens should Nonetheless, there were two impo side — or better yet, above — th tions. 46 In As the Philocleon wake of the boasted, oligarchic an revo their later dokimasia for harbourin Democracy, pp. 218-20. 47 Hansen, Athenian Democracy, p. 48 The rise of the graphe paranomon a by some scholars to the decline of o non-magistrates accountable. See J. T ernment (Madison, 1982), pp. 153-8. 49 On the graphe paranomon, see H 50 Cf. Peter Euben's analysis of the Youth (Princeton, 1997), n.21, p. 97. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 199 voting in the ekklesia and the large panels of citizen Jurors were u able, both individually and collectively. Citizens could not be cal explain their votes in either forum, nor could they be held responsible they voted. While decisions of the Assembly could be overturned, t dure for doing so (as with the graphe paranomon) assigned responsib the poor decision to the orator who made the proposal, not the demos of the demos) that voted for it (as we saw in Xenophon's account of math of Arginusae). Thus, at least on the level of formal institutio prominent political actors — the Assemblyman and the Juror — wer hold political actors to account without themselves being made acco Why this should have been so is an interesting question with multi sible explanations. Hansen and others have sought to explain it by inv epistemic assumption central to democratic ideology about the superi the judging demos: the demos is never blamed, individually or colle because it is very unlikely — or impossible — that it is truly at faul given case of bad decision-making.51 Yet quite apart from any episte fication of the practice, blaming the demos or juries for poor decis well have been considered incompatible with the Athenian understa democracy as a system that empowered the people. On this view, th leged position of the judging demos within the institutions of account Athens was consonant with — perhaps required by — the basic democracy. It is also possible that the Athenians did not believe that vidual's voting behaviour could be so egregious as to rise to the level ishable offence.52 And if it would not have made sense to hold any i accountable for his vote, neither would it have been particularly fe hold the demos or a jury collectively responsible. First, most, if not anisms of accountability at Athens were directed at holding ind rather than corporate bodies, accountable; this principle was what m collective trial of the generals after Arginusae so shocking and so u teristic.53 Nor is it clear how one could effectively hold the Assembly collectively accountable; to punish thousands of citizens for how th 51 Hansen, Athenian Democracy, p. 207. 52 The status of Jurors and Assemblymen as idiotai ('private citizens'), as o politeuomenoi or archontes (citizens taking very active roles in politics and m is crucial, in my view, to understanding how and why Athenians thought it legi leave them unaccountable. Judicial rhetoric abounds with references to an in status as an idiotes as a reason to treat him leniently or not to prosecute Demosthenes 19.182, 24.66; Aeschines 1.195). To the degree that Jurors and A men were seen as idiotai, then, they were not taken to be fit objects of Athens' f machinery of accountability. 53 See Hansen, Athenian Democracy, p. 221, for one possible exception rule — magistrates sitting on boards could be collectively suspended from off ing a vote of the Assembly until a Court could convene to consider any charg them (apocheirotonia). This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 200 in M. LANDAUER making absurd. a poor Thus, decision while would there may ha h Jurors and Assemblymen, individu system of accountability, their spe general rule. Some scholars might argue that the contrast between an unaccountable demos and a host of other accountable political actors is overdrawn. Elizabeth Markovits, for example, claims that Athenian democracy was characterized by a spirit of mutual accountability, whereby all citizens felt accountable to one another. She adduces as evidence for her claim the 'spirit of civic-mindedness' among Athenian citizens; the dokimasia that all citizens underwent when enrolling in their demes at age eighteen; ostracism, which could be used against any citizen whatsoever; the requirement of Jurors to give oaths; and the informal power of gossip, with potential social sanctions for those who mignt act poorly in tne Assemoiy or tne Law Lourts. reter Luoen nas like wise argued that Athens possessed a 'generalized culture of accountability', pointing to the dokimasia and the euthunai as its main institutional embodi ments.55 While all of these factors may have shaped citizen behaviour, it is clear that Jurors and Assemblymen faced a very different sort of scrutiny than the one faced by other citizens active in politics.56 This asymmetry in the accountability relationship had real political effects, in particular when mass groups of unaccountable citizens had the power to hold others accountable. It is against the backdrop of the Athenian demos' s privileged position within the system of accountability — the fact that they were themselves unaccountable while able to hold others to account — that the practice of parrhesia at Ath ens, and the discourse surrounding it, must be understood. Flattery and Parrhesia at Athens Recall that there were two ways in which parrhesia could feature in the autocrat-adviser relationship, given the power asymmetry between the two. Parrhesia could be granted from above, as when Isocrates urges Nicocles to 54 Markovits, Politics of Sincerity, pp. 54-5,60-1. Markovits also draws on an argu ment by Adrianne Lanni, who shows that the corona of spectators surrounding each jury trial had an effect on the behaviour of both litigators and jurors, and served the function of holding the jurors at least informally accountable. See A. Lanni, 'Spectator Sport or Seri ous Politics? Hoi periestekotes and the Athenian lawcourts', Journal of Hellenic Studies, 117 (1997). Yet the informal corona stands in marked contrast to the formal mechanisms that served to scrutinize and hold accountable most other actors in Athenian political life. 55 Euben, Corrupting Youth, p. 97. 56 Indeed, even those arguing for generalized accountability at Athens acknowledge this. In spite of Euben's claim that, at Athens, 'people were scrutinized and held account able anytime they proposed or opposed an action or decision', he also admits that 'for better or worse, members of the juries and nonspeakers in the Athenian Assembly [i.e. voters] . .. were not subject to the same intense scrutiny' (ibid., pp. 97-8). This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 201 'grant parrhesia' to his trusted advisers. Parrhesia could also be practised independently of such a privilege, as when Diodotus spoke frankly to the 'Asian potentates' he advised, even though to do so carried the risk that he would be ignored, unrewarded for his efforts or, worse, punished for his frank ness. Given the parallels between unaccountable demos and unaccountable autocrat established in the previous section, we can now see that parrhesia at Athens could feature in the orator-demos relationship in the same two ways. In his display speech On the Peace, Isocrates imagines critically rebuking his fellow citizens: I know that it is hazardous to oppose your views and that, although this is a free government [demokratia], there exists no 'freedom of speech' [parrhesia] except that which is enjoyed in this Assembly by the most senseless orators, who care nothing for you [tois aphronestatois kai meden humonphrontizousin], and in the theater by the comic poets.57 Isocrates identifies the cause of this state of affairs in the preceding passages of the speech, echoing the language of his warnings to Nicocles and Antipater. The Athenians have refused to hear speeches from anyone except those 'who accede in what [they] desire'.58 They recognize the dangers 'flatterers [ton kolakeuontonY pose in their personal lives but place 'greater confidence in them [mallon toutois pisteuontesY than in their franker fellow citizens 'when it comes to public matters'.59 As Isocrates argues: You have made the orators care for and investigate, not what will be advan tageous for the city, but how they can speak to win your favor. And the majority of them are now inclined to speak in that way. For it is clear to all that you will take pleasure in those calling you to war rather than in those counseling peace.60 Thus, just as in autocratic regimes, a vicious circle arises, with political advis ers telling the demos what they think it wants to hear, and the demos reinforc ing this habit by only listening to those speakers. Isocrates had advised Nicocles to 'grantparrhesia' to trusted advisers; in noting that 'there exists no parrhesia' in Athens, he stresses that the demos has failed to do so. The con sequences for the democracy are potentially grave: in the case Isocrates has in mind, the Athenians refuse to listen to those speakers advocating peace with their enemies, and instead are persuaded to carry on a costly war. The institu tional context is also worth stressing: Isocrates claims that parrhesia does not exist because the demos — freed like the autocrat from the burdens of being held accountable, and able to punish and reward its advisers at will — has 57 Isocrates, On the Peace, ] 58 Ibid., para. 3. 59 Ibid., para. 4. 60 Ibid., para. 5. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 202 M. begun LANDAUER to fall prey to the kind breeds. In his lectures onparrhesia, Foucault interprets Isocrates' speech as a sign of a 'crisis of democratic institutions'. In his view, by Isocrates' time, parrhesia had ceased to function properly. Flattering orators, telling audi ences only what they wanted to hear, left no space for the 'honest orator' who 'has the ability, and is courageous enough, to oppose the demos'. There is a fundamental opposition between the will of the demos and the best interests of the city; because of this, 'real parrhesia, parrhesia in its positive, critical sense, does not exist where democracy exists'.61 Foucault's interpretation cor rectly identifies many of the key features of Isocrates' argument — the prob lem of flattery and the tension between the will of the people and what Isocrates takes to be the best interests of the city — but his conclusion strikes me as misguided. Isocrates' speech, I think, is better read not as evidence for the decline of parrhesia in the fourth century but as highlighting an important way in which parrhesia operated: parrhesia, understood as the virtue of bold, risky speech, was necessary precisely because the unaccountable demos was unwilling — or unable — to grant orators parrhesia, i.e. to guarantee them the privilege of speaking frankly. Our understanding of parrhesia as a corner stone of democratic ideology has to be supplemented by emphasizing that, at least in the Assembly, it was often a kind of remedial practice necessitated by the institutional power of the demos. This view also underscores the need for a reappraisal of the role of risk in the practice of parrhesia in Athens. The dangers of speaking in the Assembly are often portrayed in contemporary scholarship as a means of making orators accountable to the demos for the advice that they gave.62 Monoson, Markovits and others have argued that parrhesia played an important vetting role in this system of accountability: an orator speaking with parrhesia willingly shoul dered the burden of that risk in the best interests of the city, and his willing ness to do so counted as evidence for his public-spiritedness. The conclusion drawn, then, is that ' [t]he risks [the orators faced] were not thought by the Athenians to undermine or even conflict with the practice of frank speech. Rather, the risks affirmed that the speaker could be held accountable for the advice ventured.'63 But as Isocrates' analysis suggests, the riskiness of speak ing to the demos, which was the consequence of the power asymmetry between the demos and its advisers, could just as easily lead to flattery as it could to parrhesia. Monoson recognizes this problem in the autocratic case: 61 M. Foucault, Fearless Speech (Los Angeles, 2001), pp. 82-3. 62 See Monoson, Entanglements, p. 55; Markovits, Politics of Sincerity, ch. 2. 63 Monoson, Entanglements, p. 55. Cf. Balot, 'Free Speech', pp. 244-6, who argues that the thorubos, viewed positively by a number of scholars, could have detrimental effects on democratic debate for reasons similar to those I discuss here in reference to the asymmetrical accountability relationship between the orators and the demos. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms o PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 203 'a tyrant's arbitrary, unaccountable, and absolute power virtually p that individuals would risk saying anything other than what the tyran to hear'.64 Yet she does not recognize the parallels between the tyran tion and the situation of the demos, and thereby does not grasp the co of the relationship between parrhesia and Athenian democracy. One might argue that Isocrates' presentation of the parallel dynam parrhesia in autocracies and Athens comprises a warped, 'Isocratean' the democracy that Athenian democrats themselves would not have a Yet the analysis of these parallels was not limited to critics of the dem In many respects, Demosthenes' analysis of parrhesia's presence (and in the Athenian Assembly shares much with the Isocratean view. In t Philippic, Demosthenes complains — speaking with parrhesia — ens, famous for allowing a measure of parrhesia even to slaves and ers, nonetheless has banished it from Assembly debate. Rather than l to good advice, the demos is flattered by pleasant speeches, with th that the city runs great risks: I think, men of Athens, that if I speak something of the truth frankly [m parrhesia], none of you will on that account become angry with m look at it this way. In other matters you think it is so necessary for there general freedom of speech [parrhesian .. . koinen] for everyone in the that you even allow aliens and slaves to share in it... but from your de ations you have banished it altogether. Hence the result is that in Assembly your self-complacency is flattered by hearing none but plea speeches, but your policy and your practice are already involving you i gravest peril.65 In this passage, Demosthenes invokes both of the senses of parrhesia have explored throughout this article. On the one hand, Demosthen that granting the privilege of parrhesia is a practice the Athenians pr selves on, to the extent that perhaps even foreigners and slaves share Demosthenes also points out that this privilege is not properly secure Assembly — indeed, it is 'banished altogether'. Yet this does not me Demosthenes cannot speak frankly (after all, he is doing so, or claim doing so, in this very speech). But it does mean that he has to practis tue of parrhesia from below, in the face of potential censure, and mus the risk that entails. And it is far from clear that Demosthenes thinks t 64 Monoson, Entanglements, p. 55. 65 Demosthenes, Loeb, Vol. 1, Orations, trans. J.H. Vince (Cambridge, M 9.3-9.4. Cf. Carter's discussion of this passage in 'Citizen Attribute, Negati pp. 208-9. 66 Cf. Demosthenes, Orations, 15.1: Ί think it necessary, men of Athens, when deciding about such great matters, to grant parrhesia (didonai parrhesian) to each of your advisers.' In this passage, too, Demosthenes takes parrhesia to be a privilege that can be granted, using the same language (didonai parrhesian) as Isocrates offers to Nicocles (see note 22, above). This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 204 M. LANDAUER helps to ensure good debate; rather encouraged flattery, at least on the Despite these similarities, Demosth in two respects. First, unlike Isocr Demosthenes directly challenges parrhesia in the Assembly even speech is not encouraged and may pic and On the Chersonese, Demost the flattery of his fellow orators, that Isocrates merely preached. Sec analysis of what he takes to be t debate: the corruption of the de repeats his critique of Assembly d batim in On the Chersonese, he blam of to Assembly such a debate: frame of 'by mind persuasive that in your and have no ear but for complimen you are at this moment running th to hold the demos primarily respon the demos has all but forced the ora the orators are to blame. Demosthenes further explores the dynamics of oratorical corruption of the demos in the Third Olynthiac. The problems the Athenians face can be traced back to the 'popularity hunting [pros charin demegorein]' of some of the ora tors.69 Rather than proposing good public policy, the orators ply the demos with questions such as 'what would you like? What shall I propose? How can I oblige you?'.70 One might be tempted to take such an assertion as support for an Isocratean analysis of the power asymmetry between demos or autocrat and advisers. The obsequious questions the orators ask could be seen as the natural response to their inferior position — they can profit only by offering 67 The claim that the demos will only listen to flatterers finds perhaps its most famous exposition in Plato's Gorgias, where Socrates identifies rhetoric as a 'part of flattery' and argues that this kind of persuasive speech finds its natural home in the presence of large, uninformed audiences (Plato's characterization of the dikasteria and ekklesia)·, see Gorgias, 459a-466a. I am not merely arguing that the flattery of the orators has to be understood within the context of the asymmetric accountability relationship between demos and orator; I am also arguing that parrhesia, at least in its manifestation as risky speech, has to be understood as arising from this same context. The risky practice of parrhesia is an alternative to flattery, and a potential remedy to it, but its very riskiness underlines the fact that it is a product of the institutional circumstances that too often pro duce flattery, not frank speech. 68 Demosthenes, Orations, 8.34. 69 Ibid., 3.3. 70 Ibid., 3.22. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 205 the demos exactly what it wants. Strikingly, however, Demosthenes seems draw the opposite conclusion. Contrasting Assembly debate before the proc of corruption began and its current state, Demosthenes says the following: What is the cause of all this, and why, pray, did everything go well then that now goes amiss? Because then the people, having the courage to act and to fight, were the master [despotes] of the politicians and were themselves the dispensers of all favours [kurios autos hapanton ton agathon}·, the rest were well content to accept at the people's hand honour and authority and reward. Now, on the contrary, the politicians hold the purse-strings and manage everything, while you, the people, robbed of nerve and sinew, stripped of wealth and of allies, have sunk to the level of lackeys and hangers on [en huperetou kai prosthekes merei gegenesthe] ...71 The flattery and obsequiousness of the orators, Demosthenes claims, is no sign of the demos's power but rather of that power's usurpation by a few. some extent, Demosthenes is exaggerating the powerlessness of the demos here for rhetorical effect: using the image of a debased and weakened dem Demosthenes hopes to shame the Assembly into adopting his activist a energetic policies against the Macedonians. His argument is still ultimatel premised on the demos being the chief decision maker: the obsequious que tions of the orators only make sense given this premise, as does the very oc sion for Demosthenes to give the speech. If the demos could not change i policies as it saw fit, there would be no point in Demosthenes attempting persuade it. Yet by highlighting the orators' role in starting up the vicious cle of flattery, Demosthenes both minimizes the responsibility the demo bears in the situation and points to a way forward: if the orators were not out corrupt, and the demos were more jealous of its own sovereignty and mindf of its own good, the vicious circle could be avoided.72 Demosthenes is also making an important observation here about the power dynamics betwee 71 Ibid., 3.30-31. 72 It is worth contrasting Demosthenes' and Isocrates' responses to the pathologies Assembly debate with Diodotus' in Thucydides' account of the Mytilenean debate. Mary Dietz has noted, Diodotus is speaking within 'an already corrupted situation which his desire not to be punished by the demos and his agonal struggle with Cleo supervene on his attempt to persuade the Athenians of what he takes to be the best cou of action. See M. Dietz, Turning Operations (New York, 2002), p. 157. Diodotus' cussion of accountability in diagnosing the 'corrupted' state of Assembly debate is ticularly salient. As he tells the demos: 'we, your advisers, are responsible, while yo our audience are not so. For if those of you who gave the advice, and those who took suffered equally, you would judge more calmly; as it is, you visit the disasters into whi the whim of the moment may have led you, upon the single person of your adviser, upon yourselves, his numerous companions in error.' (Thucydides, 3.43.5). Strikingl Diodotus, while recognizing the asymmetry of accountability between demos and o tor, seems to call less for relaxing the potential sanctions on orators (although cf. 3.4 than for extending such sanctions to the demos. Diodotus' solution, then, might be for burdens of accountability to be shared more equally, rather than to be sloughed This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 206 M. LANDAUER flattering ruler's adviser own and power. a decision This ma happens policies, but also because once the starts up, it becomes difficult to s demos using the orators or is it bei The ambiguity of the power relati reminiscent of Aristotle's analysis, ship between the demos and demag Aristotle's account, while confirm points to its limits. In the final for consider Athens an example — Ari tude [to plethos], have the suprem law by their decrees' ,73 In Aristotl that leads to demagoguery and fla then demagogues arise'. Aristotle go the power of the demos closely res regimes, flatterers are honoured.74 to the tyrannical demos, the analysi blurred: 'For it happens that they [ demos has the supreme power over power over the opinion of the p them.'75 In such regimes, Aristotl tvrant and tool of the orators. Both Aristotle and Demosthenes, ambiguities of the orator-demos r on the institutional basis for that r voluntarist solution to the problem reined in by the demos; rather, Ar such a relationship between demos flawed. Where the demos has unlim ters, Aristotle claims, flattery is t itly deny that, even under such cir challenge the demos and speak wit this would be a likely outcome. Of course, if Aristotle's solution t democracy, entirely. subordinate Unfortunately, I do to not the have l th to discuss its implications. See also Sax sion of Diodotus' and Cleon's speeches a Silence and Democracy (University Pa Diodotus' speech and the question of co 73 Aristotle, Politics, 1292a5-8. 74 75 Ibid., 1292al8-20. Ibid., 1292a26-28. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms PARRHESIA AND THE DEMOS TYRANNOS 207 matters, then his solution is not one an Athenian democrat co Indeed, a good democrat would reject Aristotle's framing of the pr counter that the people, judging matters in the courts and the Ass actually the best guardians of the rule of law, not its undermine Aeschines' argument from his Against Ctesiphon, where the dem to judge matters and hold elites accountable are held up as great defending the rule of law: Tyrannies and oligarchies are administered according to the tem their lords, but democratic states according to their own establishe Let no man among you forget this, but let each bear distinctly in m when he enters a court-room to sit as juror in a suit against an illega [graphe paranomon], on that day he is to cast his vote for or against freedom of speech [parrhesia].76 Aeschines, in calling on the Athenians here to defend the rule of tinuing to hold elites accountable, may have been correct that the p ordinary citizens — understood as the privilege of speaking frankly, and which Athens prided itself on promoting — depend robust popular control of elites, who might otherwise attempt to su cratic norms and institutions. But in defending the graphe paranom also calling for the preservation of an institution that made the frank speech in the Assembly rarer, riskier and more difficult. Conclusion The contrast between flattery and parrhesia, and the parallels between the institutional positions of the tyrant and the demos, complicate our understand ing of the conceptualization and practice of parrhesia in Athens. Far from marking off a clear boundary between tyrannical and democratic regimes, the discourse surrounding parrhesia in Athens often highlighted the similarities between the demos and the autocrat. While both the autocrat and the demos could 'grant parrhesia' to their advisers, such freedom was not a foregone conclusion. Absent this privilege, advisers could still practise the virtue of risky parrhesia in addressing their audiences, but parrhesia in this sense is therefore a remedial mode of advising unaccountable decision makers who have the power to hold their advisers to account. The above analysis thus emphasizes the ways in which the practice of parrhesia in many contexts was predicated on inequalities and asymmetries of power. Our understanding of parrhesia's egalitarian, democratic overtones should be accordingly modified. Placing that power asymmetry at the centre of the analysis of parrhesia suggests a distinction important for our understanding Athenian Assembly debate more generally. Parrhesia is less a norm for deliberation than it is a norm for counsel. Athens was not a deliberative democracy but a democracy 76 Aeschines, Against Ctesiphon, para. 6. This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms 208 M. LANDAUER with a sovereign demos and a host between autocratic and democratic ing advice they both invite, suggests cal discussion and strong popular con Quite to the contrary, there was a p of elites, as institutionalized in the and high quality political debate, if t of flattery. It is true that even whe granted, parrhesia was still a practic of flattery — but this required an or ply of orators willing to take those a problem endemic to the Assembly to popular control of elites and to d does not mean that these commitme Matthew Landauer HARVARD UNIVERSITY 77 What I have been calling flattery in this article als with what Simone Chambers has recently called 'pleb bers, 'Rhetoric and the Public Sphere: Has Deliberativ Democracy?', Political Theory, 37 (2009), pp. 323-5 understanding of plebiscitary rhetoric, exemplified in the lack of 'dialogic accountability' between orator dialogic accountability does not mean that the relations lack of accountability; instead, the accountability relations assembled citizens able to hold the orators accountabl may have precluded the citizens from enjoying the epist opposed to rhetoric-infused counsel), it did allow them cal elites. Thus one way of understanding my analysis of p is as an attempt to explore the relationship between instit thriving practice of plebiscitary rhetoric in the Atheni point, the relevance of the Athenian case to contempor for we too have institutions of accountability that may be plebiscitary rhetoric — elections and campaigns come t should be mindful of the potential tradeoff between h and encouraging sound political discussion, particularly ability and high-quality debate sometimes seem to be in This content downloaded from 150.216.68.200 on Wed, 03 Jan 2018 14:39:30 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms